Knowledge

On Ancient Medicine

Source 📝

136:
organ responsible for mental diseases. He held that the four fluids blood, phlegm, yellow bile, and black bile as well as observation, study of the reasons, balance of theory, and the four liquids themselves form the basis for the diagnosis and treatment of both physical and mental illnesses. According to Plato's view, there are two possible ways to repair the body and the soul. While medicine and gymnastics are seen as legitimate remedies, the legislative and judicial systems are necessary for true soul healing. The betterment of human conduct and the treatment of both mental and physical diseases depended heavily on music and theater. It was thought that using music to heal the spirit also treated the body, along with particular musical treatments for particular illnesses. The first person to use music as treatment to overcome pain was Asclepius. According to Aristotle, religious music that uplifts the spirit has a similar impact on individuals who have undergone therapy and mental catharsis. "Catharsis," or the letting go of emotions via performance, took place in the Theater of Epidaurus in the Ancient Temple of Epidaurus.
245:
skills to include preparation and administration of prescriptions or remedies. This is critical because the same illness manifests itself differently in each patient and treatment must correspond to individual symptoms, and not to the common symptoms. This also applies to dietary measures. Thus, in the preparation and administration of remedies or dietary measures, care must be given not only in selecting the quantity and quality of the preparation or remedy, but also to the timing of its administration which must take into account bodily rhythms. The physician, the author argues, must rely upon the reaction of the individual to the treatment. This is indeed a complex process which demands both the education and precision of the physician. Hippocrates argues that even if the ancient art of medicine "does not possess precision in everything; rather, since it has been able to come, by means of reasoning, from profound ignorance close to perfect accuracy, I think it much more appropriate to marvel at its discoveries as having been made admirably, correctly, and not by chance".
211:
the cure for each disease is the opposite of the cause. The author imagines a situation where a person changes his food from cooked to raw and as a result becomes ill. Thus, the cause of a given illness is associated with a given humor and the cure as being that humor's opposite. Hot therefore would cure cold, and dry would be the cure for wet. The author sees this as an oversimplification. He argues that cooking is a process in which the original raw food losses some of its qualities and gains others by mixing and blending (13.3). Human beings are affected by the food they consume because every food has its own innate virtues. It is important for the physician to identify these virtues (14.1-2). The attainment of such knowledge demands a clear understanding of human nature. The human being, explains the author, contains a blend of many humors. When the humors are balanced or properly mixed the human being is healthy, but when they are unbalanced or improperly mixed and one is more concentrated than the other, pain and disease is the result (14.4-6).
203:
experience and discovery. It should be empirical in its methodology. Hence, in chapter 2 the author argues that medicine's principle and method enables the physician to make discoveries over a long period of time. The discipline must be flexible and receptive to new discoveries. In chapters 3–8, the author supports the claim that medicine has a method of discovery by giving an account of medicine's origins and discoveries. He traces it back to a regimen beneficial for the sick and observes that some foods are not beneficial for either the healthy or the sick. The author cites accounts of human beings from the fifth-century who suffered as a result of their savage diet. As a result, techniques were developed for the preparation of food best suited in producing a healthy and civilized human being. He likens it to a medical discovery (3.4-6); and as such constitutes a general
236:
the theory of human nature must be based on medicine, through the observation of the human organism within nature. He takes exception to thinkers such as Empedocles who attempted to provide such an understanding through his cosmological theories. Practically speaking, for medicine to be effective the physician needs to know the true nature of man and this must be determined through his relationship to food, drink, and other practices associated with the human organism (20.3). Therefore, the physician must understand the constituency of food and its effects on the body of the patient he is treating. In Chapters 22–24 the author extends the nature theory to include bodily structures. He also expands his theory of knowledge by advocating the use of analogies to attain an understanding of that which cannot be observed directly within the human organism.
215:
examples from common experience. For instance, in a fever hot and cold humors counteract each other in the body without the need of medical aid. As he points out in chapter 17, however, in some cases the fever persists. This is an indication that hot is not the sole cause of the fever. There must be some other inherent factor responsible for sustaining the fever. In chapters 18 and 19, he continues to develop the idea that recovery from disease comes about when there is a blending and coction of the humors. Coction is the act or process of attaining a more perfect or more desirable condition. The importance of coction in the author's theory also reflects his close analogy between medicine and cooking. Just as the cook brings about coction in food external to the human organism; the physician brings about coction of the bodily humors.
207:. The author establishes a close methodological parallel between cooking and medicine. In cooking it is critical to recognize that human beings have a nature distinct from animals. For instance, humans are less capable of digesting raw meats. Thus, allowances must be made in the preparation and cooking of meat that best suit the human metabolism (3.5). The most common element between cooking and medicine is the mixing and blending of foods. Medicine, however, requires a greater discrimination between food types and classes of individuals so that correct nutritional needs may be identified and prescribed (5). The practitioner in the end acquires mastery of preparing foods and the ability to identify the class of individuals to whom the food is administered. In this regard, cooking and medicine are the same (chaps. 7–8). 167:: earth, water, air, and fire. On the basis of these four elements he sought to account for the origin of matter. Matter or the universe was generated out of these four elements and their mutual attraction and repulsion. The conflict between these two schools of thought became manifest in their medical philosophies. Whereas, Alcmaeon argued that there were indefinite number of diverse qualities that made up the human organism, Empedocles contended that there were four concrete or substantial elements. Whereas it is Empedocles' medical philosophy that ultimately inspires the humoral doctrine of human nature, it is Alcmaeon's theory that underpins the medical therapeutic doctrine proposed in 94:(nature) or unitary vital force of the organism by which the physician must be guided. It is the self-healing powers of the human organism, the inner physician, which must always be consulted in the diagnosis and treatment of sickness. The interaction of the humors within man must always be seen in this light. Indeed, this group viewed the human organism as being composed of an infinite number of humors and that disease consists in the isolation of one of these humors within the organism leading to an imbalance which must be cured through coction of this humor, a process leading to the restoration of balance. 156:, while Croton harbored the Pythagorean sect of medical philosophy. The school of Agrigentum and Empedocles placed great emphasis on cure by contraries and thus should be associated with Group III of the Hippocratic Corpus. The school of Croton rejected the notion of cure by contraries while championing the medical philosophy that perceived the human organism consists of an infinite number of humors. The arguments of this group should be identified with Group IV of the Hippocratic Corpus. 190:
critiques the hypothesis theory proposed by his opponents as being an oversimplified conception of the cause of disease. Against this backdrop, he discusses his own theory and method he employed in its discovery (chaps. 20–24). He then responds to the charge that ancient medicine is not a genuine medical art because it has limited accuracy. These arguments must be seen in the light of the author's theory of human physiology (chaps. 9–12).
102:
Diseases and their causes are categorized as are their respective remedies. It places emphasis on cure by contraries and largely ignores the concept of the self-healing capacity of the organism. The organism and its environment are analyzed in terms of hypothesized causal processes. Treatment consists in opposing the humor, quality or power causing the disease by administering a remedy of opposite quality.
660: 224: 33: 171:(Group IV). Alcmaeon's argument that there are an infinite number of causes for disease that cannot be simply organized into categories is the basic operating assumption of empirical medicine. Therefore, medical knowledge continuously expanded thorough a firsthand experience and observation of the human organism within nature. It is in this light that 163:. Alcmaeon argued that the maintenance of good health required a balance of the powers of moist and dry, cold and hot, bitter and sweet. Sickness arises when there is an imbalance within the human organism caused by the predominance of one power over another. In the Agrigentum school of thought Empedocles hypothesized that the universe consisted of 132:
after treating the wounds with pure water or wine, they needed to be kept dry in order to heal correctly and rapidly. Also, he thought that the development of pus contributed to the decrease of wound complications. These discoveries influenced surgical treatment procedures for wounds and injuries up to the Middle Ages.
135:
The earliest taxonomy of mental illnesses was proposed by Hippocrates, and it included mania, melancholy, phrenitis, insanity, disobedience, paranoia, panic, epilepsy, and hysteria. He held that intellect and sensitivity enter the brain through the lips by breathing and that the brain is the primary
122:
To enhance both physical and mental health, physical movement was an essential component of academic learning. Special services were offered by teachers known as "paidotrivai" during the Olympic Games. According to a study by Hippocrates, olive oil was used to warm up, increase body temperature, and
282:
There are two main proponents when discussing the influences on the treatise, whether of philosophy on medicine or the reverse. Hans Diller attempted to show that the author's point of view was influenced mostly by Plato. Ludwig Edelstein argued the author characterized 'Hippocratic empiricism', "a
210:
It is in chapter 13 that the author returns to his analysis of his opponent's hypothesis theory. His goal is to explore the potential consequences of the principle in question. The proponents of cure by contraries assume that all diseases have their roots in the humors hot, cold, wet, dry, and that
131:
Up until the Middle Ages, Hippocrates and Galen had quite an impact on surgical treatment procedures for wounds and injuries. For instance, Hippocrates identified the splitting of limb gangrene and treated the ailment by making incisions between the dead and the living tissue.  He thought that
118:
To maintain health, Ancient Greeks followed the belief that physical and mental health work together. Aristotle believed that the best way to achieve harmony between the mind and body is to participate in sports and gymnastics. It has been suggested that sessions of aerobic for example walking will
114:
The medical practice of Hippocrates used natural aspects to treat diseases. The Hippocratic teachings on the value of knowing a patient's health, independence of thought, and the necessity for balance between the individuals, the social environment, and the natural environment. These foundations of
244:
In chapters 9–12 the author argues that there is a corresponding relationship between the physician's experience and knowledge and his ability to practice the art of medicine. The greater the general and specific knowledge attained by the physician, the more accurate his diagnostic and therapeutic
235:
In chapter 20 the author dismisses the theories of human nature associated with Empedocles and the pre-Socratic inquiry as irrelevant to medical practices. He argues that their theories lean towards philosophy and have more to do with the art of writing than with medicine. The author believes that
105:
Group IV: This group according to Harris Coulter, "Consists of two works: Ancient Medicine and The Art. These two works provide analysis and critique of the therapeutic doctrine of Group three. The idea of cure through opposition between qualities is rejected, and a philosophical justification is
86:
theory of medicine proposed that our bodies were made up of diverse fluids, elements, or powers, that were considered to be the basic units or fundamental building blocks of all nature. Whereas, a more simplified and categorized version of this theory is usually associated with the four humors of
214:
In chapter 15 the author argues that whereas the proponents of humoral medicine see food purely as hot, cold, wet, or dry, human beings also possess a quality such as sweet or bitter. These qualities are the ones that cause serious harm to the body. In Chapter 16, the author presents a number of
97:
Group II: The proponents of this group argue that in addition to cure through coction and evacuation may be added the therapeutic approach of treatment of sickness through the administration of contraries. This could be in the form of dietary prescription but also medicinal substances. Medicinal
70:
Hippocrates was born circa 460 BCE on the island of Cos in Greece. Hippocrates was looked at as a teacher and physician. His name is in around sixty medical articles, most of these medical articles were not written by him. He is admired for his high standards of moral conduct in the practice of
189:
have three components. In chapters 1–19 the author responds to the supporters of the hypothesis theory of medicine. In so doing he argues that the exploration of medicine itself reveals the human organism as a blend of diverse substances or humors. Having set forth this humoral theory, he then
101:
Group III: This group utilizes an analytical approach to the diagnosis and treatment of sickness. It relies on the formation of hypotheses based on systematized views of the humoral activity and their corresponding treatments. Its medical theory could be described as rational versus empirical.
257:
span from 440 to around 350 BC. There are a number of considerations which strongly suggest a date in the late fifth century. That the author refers to Empedocles (490–430 B.C.) as motivation of the method he attacks suggests a date not long after his peak of activity. The author's sense of
202:
depends on the knowledge of the physician attained through first-hand experience that enables him to both distinguish diverse treatments and to realize success in their skillful administration (1). Medicine should not proceed with hypotheses or generalizations; rather it should be rooted in
283:
methodological stance characterized by the rejection of all generalizations and resulting from the influence of Protagorean relativism on medical thought." The proponents for tracing influence in the opposite direction, from medicine to philosophy, argued that the work
62:, (c. 460 BC – c. 370 BC) the father of Western medicine, philological evidence now suggests that it was written over a period of several centuries and stylistically seems to indicate that it was the product of many authors dating from about 450–400 B.C. 87:
black bile, blood, phlegm and yellow bile, the humoral theory as presented in Group I of the Hippocratic Corpus is never structured or schematized. Its approach to understanding the diverse cause of illnesses and their cures is empirical in nature.
303:
has been scrutinized to aid in answering the 'Hippocratic question': the question about which of the works in the Hippocratic corpus were written by Hippocrates. Littré was the scholar most associated with advocating that
258:
discovery and benefits of technology are characteristic of late fifth-century thought. The idea that human beings through technology rose from savage behavior has parallels in Sophocles' fifth-century work,
262:. Furthermore, the author's attack on the written account of medicine by sophists as having nothing to do with the art of medicine is a discussion taken up by the fifth-century thinker Socrates in 198:
The author is responding to the supporters of the hypothesis theory by arguing that medicine has a systematic character to qualify it as a tekhne (art, craft or science). This genuine
287:
influenced Protagoras. It is possible, however, that different thinkers could come to similar conclusions regarding natural philosophy and practice independently of one another.
175:
should be seen as an attempt by the advocates of the Alcmaeon and the empirical school of thought to respond to and critique the Empedoclean or humoral theory of medicine.
98:
substances are chosen on the basis of their indwelling powers or virtues, a method of analysis also applied in the diagnosis of disease in relation to the human organism.
144:
The origins of the Hippocratic Corpus can be traced in the sixth and fifth centuries B.C. in Italy. There were two seminal schools of Western medical thought; there was
468: 90:
It therefore, takes a more holistic view of the human organism which defines simple categorization of disease causality and treatment or cure. It places emphasis on
691: 79:
On the basis of its diverse arguments regarding the nature of medical therapeutics, the Hippocratic Corpus could be divided into four divisions or groups.
71:
medicine, especially for the Hippocratic Oath, which was also written by someone else. Hippocrates later dies circa 375 BCE in Larissa, Thessaly.
123:
become more flexible, and athletes were given figs as well as other fruits containing high glucose concentrations to help them perform better.
58:. The Corpus itself is a collection of about sixty writings covering all areas of medical thought and practice. Traditionally associated with 686: 664: 312:. However, it is difficult to reconstruct the historical Hippocrates with our existing evidence amounting to a brief account in the 696: 119:
help to boost cognitive attention control in children. Data suggests that exercise improves scholastic performance.
427:
Kleisiaris CF, Sfakianakis C, Papathanasiou IV, Kleisiaris CF, Sfakianakis C, Papathanasiou IV (March 15, 2014).
115:
health were incorporated in Ancient Greece to help discover the source of illness and to help promote health.
631:
Divided Legacy: A History of the Schism in Medical Thought: The Patterns Emerge: Hippocrates to Paracelsus 1
266:. Also, the treatise's interest of 'things in the sky and under the earth' also characterizes Aristophanes' 401:
Divided Legacy: A History of the Schism in Medical thought: The Patterns Emerge: Hippocrates to Paracelsus
386:
Divided Legacy: A History of the Schism in Medical thought: The Patterns Emerge: Hippocrates to Paracelsus
368:
Divided Legacy: A History of the Schism in Medical thought: The Patterns Emerge: Hippocrates to Paracelsus
353:
Divided Legacy: A History of the Schism in Medical thought: The Patterns Emerge: Hippocrates to Paracelsus
316:
papyrus, and a few references in Plato and Aristotle. Based on the information available for the treatise
462: 308:
was written by Hippocrates. He thought that the treatise was the work to which Plato was referring in
160: 55: 296: 450: 164: 440: 670: 445: 428: 47: 644: 680: 337: 59: 17: 659: 153: 145: 223: 454: 83: 32: 228: 149: 152:
on the west coast of the Gulf of Taranto. Agrigentum was the home of
320:, it is impossible to definitively answer the Hippocratic question. 231:
of the reduction of a dislocated shoulder with a Hippocratic device
222: 31: 429:"Health care practices in ancient Greece: The Hippocratic ideal" 54:) is perhaps the most intriguing and compelling work of the 159:
The first medical philosopher of the school of Croton was
106:
given for the ideas underlying the works of Group 1."
655:, ed. J. L. Heiberg, Leipzig/Berlin, 1927, pp. 36–55. 673:
compiled by John Porter, University of Saskatchewan.
433:Journal of Medical Ethics and History of Medicine 52:Περὶ Ἀρχαίας Ἰατρικῆς; Latin: De vetere medicina 561:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. pp. 33–35. 546:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. pp. 30–31. 501:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. pp. 25–26. 403:. Washington DC: Wehawken Book. pp. 8–9. 8: 467:: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list ( 591:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. pp. 1–5. 370:. Washington DC: Wehawken Book. p. 15. 671:Scholarly Bibliography on Ancient Medicine 388:. Washington DC: Wehawken Book. p. 8. 355:. Washington DC: Wehawken Book. p. 7. 606:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. p. 65. 576:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. p. 63. 531:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. p. 28. 516:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. p. 27. 486:. Leiden: Brill Academic Pub. p. 25. 444: 299:in the nineteenth century, the treatise 328: 460: 379: 377: 7: 422: 420: 418: 416: 414: 412: 410: 253:The dates proposed by Schiefsky for 148:on the southern coast of Sicily and 633:. Washington, DC: Wehawken Book Co. 336:Smith, Wesley D. (March 14, 2023). 27:Greek medical text, c. 450–400 B.C. 692:Books about diseases and disorders 25: 127:Trauma, Therapy and Interventions 658: 622:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 604:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 589:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 574:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 559:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 544:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 529:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 514:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 499:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 484:Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine 1: 75:Hippocratic Corpus: structure 687:Ancient Greek medical works 629:Coulter, Harris L. (1975). 140:Hippocratic Corpus: origins 713: 110:Ancient Medicine in Greece 51: 620:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 602:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 587:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 572:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 557:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 542:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 527:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 512:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 497:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 482:Schiefsky, Mark (2005). 399:Coulter, Harris (1975). 384:Coulter, Harris (1975). 366:Coulter, Harris (1975). 351:Coulter, Harris (1975). 697:Books about health care 185:The basic arguments of 270:(424 BC.) and Plato's 232: 37: 314:Anonymous Londinensis 226: 35: 665:On Ancient Medicine 318:On Ancient Medicine 306:On Ancient Medicine 301:On Ancient Medicine 285:On Ancient Medicine 255:On Ancient Medicine 187:On Ancient Medicine 180:On Ancient Medicine 173:On Ancient Medicine 169:On Ancient Medicine 43:On Ancient Medicine 653:De prisca medicina 295:Since the work of 233: 161:Alcmaeon of Croton 56:Hippocratic Corpus 38: 663:Works related to 649:Hippocratis Opera 16:(Redirected from 704: 662: 634: 625: 624:. Leiden: Brill. 608: 607: 599: 593: 592: 584: 578: 577: 569: 563: 562: 554: 548: 547: 539: 533: 532: 524: 518: 517: 509: 503: 502: 494: 488: 487: 479: 473: 472: 466: 458: 448: 424: 405: 404: 396: 390: 389: 381: 372: 371: 363: 357: 356: 348: 342: 341: 333: 53: 21: 18:Ancient medicine 712: 711: 707: 706: 705: 703: 702: 701: 677: 676: 641: 628: 619: 616: 611: 601: 600: 596: 586: 585: 581: 571: 570: 566: 556: 555: 551: 541: 540: 536: 526: 525: 521: 511: 510: 506: 496: 495: 491: 481: 480: 476: 459: 426: 425: 408: 398: 397: 393: 383: 382: 375: 365: 364: 360: 350: 349: 345: 335: 334: 330: 326: 293: 280: 251: 242: 221: 196: 183: 142: 129: 112: 77: 68: 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 710: 708: 700: 699: 694: 689: 679: 678: 675: 674: 668: 656: 640: 639:External links 637: 636: 635: 626: 615: 612: 610: 609: 594: 579: 564: 549: 534: 519: 504: 489: 474: 406: 391: 373: 358: 343: 327: 325: 322: 292: 289: 279: 276: 250: 247: 241: 238: 220: 219:Chapters 20–24 217: 195: 192: 182: 177: 141: 138: 128: 125: 111: 108: 76: 73: 67: 64: 26: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 709: 698: 695: 693: 690: 688: 685: 684: 682: 672: 669: 667:at Wikisource 666: 661: 657: 654: 650: 646: 643: 642: 638: 632: 627: 623: 618: 617: 613: 605: 598: 595: 590: 583: 580: 575: 568: 565: 560: 553: 550: 545: 538: 535: 530: 523: 520: 515: 508: 505: 500: 493: 490: 485: 478: 475: 470: 464: 456: 452: 447: 442: 438: 434: 430: 423: 421: 419: 417: 415: 413: 411: 407: 402: 395: 392: 387: 380: 378: 374: 369: 362: 359: 354: 347: 344: 339: 338:"Hippocrates" 332: 329: 323: 321: 319: 315: 311: 307: 302: 298: 290: 288: 286: 277: 275: 273: 269: 265: 261: 256: 248: 246: 240:Chapters 9–12 239: 237: 230: 225: 218: 216: 212: 208: 206: 201: 194:Chapters 1–19 193: 191: 188: 181: 178: 176: 174: 170: 166: 165:four elements 162: 157: 155: 151: 147: 139: 137: 133: 126: 124: 120: 116: 109: 107: 103: 99: 95: 93: 88: 85: 82:Group I: The 80: 74: 72: 65: 63: 61: 57: 49: 45: 44: 40:The treatise 34: 30: 19: 652: 648: 630: 621: 603: 597: 588: 582: 573: 567: 558: 552: 543: 537: 528: 522: 513: 507: 498: 492: 483: 477: 463:cite journal 436: 432: 400: 394: 385: 367: 361: 352: 346: 331: 317: 313: 310:The Phaedrus 309: 305: 300: 297:Émile Littré 294: 284: 281: 271: 267: 263: 259: 254: 252: 243: 234: 213: 209: 204: 199: 197: 186: 184: 179: 172: 168: 158: 143: 134: 130: 121: 117: 113: 104: 100: 96: 91: 89: 81: 78: 69: 42: 41: 39: 29: 66:Hippocrates 60:Hippocrates 36:Hippocrates 681:Categories 645:Greek text 614:References 291:Authorship 264:The Phaedo 154:Empedocles 146:Agrigentum 278:Influence 455:25512827 260:Antigone 651:, I 1, 446:4263393 272:Apology 229:woodcut 84:humoral 453:  443:  268:Clouds 205:tekhne 200:tekhne 150:Croton 92:physis 439:: 6. 324:Notes 48:Greek 469:link 451:PMID 249:Date 647:in 441:PMC 683:: 465:}} 461:{{ 449:. 435:. 431:. 409:^ 376:^ 274:. 227:A 50:: 471:) 457:. 437:7 340:. 46:( 20:)

Index

Ancient medicine

Greek
Hippocratic Corpus
Hippocrates
humoral
Agrigentum
Croton
Empedocles
Alcmaeon of Croton
four elements

woodcut
Émile Littré
"Hippocrates"









"Health care practices in ancient Greece: The Hippocratic ideal"
PMC
4263393
PMID
25512827
cite journal

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.