Knowledge

Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation

Source 📝

2323:
Therefore, there is a way to go from a proof of 0 = 1 to a proof of any basic arithmetic equality, and thus to a proof of any complex arithmetic proposition. Furthermore, to get this result it was not necessary to invoke the Peano axiom that states that 0 is "not" the successor of any
964:
Kolmogorov followed the same lines but phrased his interpretation in terms of problems and solutions. To assert a formula is to claim to know a solution to the problem represented by that formula. For instance
1571: 1255: 1201: 1795: 1858: 1386: 1319: 707: 540: 1151: 572: 356: 284: 143: 1957: 2111: 1992: 1919: 2076: 2046: 1493: 1464: 842: 111: 2250: 252: 1103: 989: 816: 425: 2342: 2227: 1719: 1699: 1517: 1339: 925: 902: 959: 790: 655: 2270: 2207: 2187: 2163: 2143: 1878: 1739: 1679: 1659: 1639: 1619: 1591: 1438: 1414: 1275: 1069: 1049: 1029: 1009: 882: 862: 767: 747: 727: 632: 612: 592: 488: 468: 448: 396: 376: 324: 304: 223: 203: 183: 163: 2414:
does (which is always decidable for natural numbers), otherwise there is no proof. These are then built up by induction into more complex algorithms.
2538: 2548: 2390:. It deals with Heyting arithmetic, where the domain of quantification is the natural numbers and the primitive propositions are of the form 2166: 935:
The interpretation of a primitive proposition is supposed to be known from context. In the context of arithmetic, a proof of the formula
2520: 2434: 2422: 2543: 2376: 76: 1526: 1210: 1156: 2275:
A standard example of absurdity is found in dealing with arithmetic. Assume that 0 = 1, and proceed by
80: 1744: 1113: 2375:
that converts one proof to another, or that converts an element of a domain to a proof. Different versions of
2320: + 1. By induction, 0 is equal to all numbers, and therefore any two natural numbers become equal. 1813: 1347: 1280: 663: 496: 2474: 1118: 2489: 2360: 2276: 1884: 545: 329: 257: 116: 17: 1924: 2511: 2279:: 0 = 0 by the axiom of equality. Now (induction hypothesis), if 0 were equal to a certain 2485: 2470: 40: 2081: 1962: 1889: 2494: 2387: 2345: 28: 2055: 2025: 1472: 1443: 821: 90: 52: 2232: 231: 2291: 1082: 968: 798: 404: 44: 2327: 2212: 1704: 1684: 1502: 1324: 910: 887: 2515: 2418: 938: 772: 637: 2280: 2255: 2192: 2172: 2148: 2128: 2122: 1863: 1724: 1664: 1644: 1624: 1604: 1576: 1423: 1399: 1260: 1054: 1034: 1014: 994: 867: 847: 752: 732: 712: 617: 597: 577: 473: 453: 433: 381: 361: 309: 289: 208: 188: 168: 148: 64: 2532: 2383: 60: 48: 1806: 2421:
as defining the notion of a function, then the BHK interpretation describes the
928: 2371:
The BHK interpretation will depend on the view taken about what constitutes a
1959:, and in general has no proof. According to the interpretation, a proof of 2125:
to have a formal negation operator such that there is a proof of "not"
75:
The interpretation states what is intended to be a proof of a given
2316:), but since 0 = 1, therefore 0 would also be equal to 961:
is a computation reducing the two terms to the same numeral.
1804:
Indeed, the same line of thought provides a proof for the
67:. It is the standard explanation of intuitionistic logic. 2324:
natural number. This makes 0 = 1 suitable as
1797:, proving the law of non-contradiction, no matter what 2330: 2258: 2235: 2215: 2195: 2175: 2151: 2131: 2084: 2058: 2028: 1965: 1927: 1892: 1866: 1816: 1747: 1727: 1707: 1687: 1667: 1647: 1627: 1607: 1579: 1529: 1505: 1475: 1446: 1426: 1402: 1350: 1327: 1283: 1263: 1213: 1159: 1121: 1085: 1057: 1037: 1017: 997: 971: 941: 913: 890: 870: 850: 824: 801: 775: 755: 735: 715: 666: 640: 620: 600: 580: 548: 499: 476: 456: 436: 407: 384: 364: 332: 312: 292: 260: 234: 211: 191: 171: 151: 119: 93: 2475:"History of Constructivism in the Twentieth Century" 2488:(2003). "Constructivism and Proof Theory (draft)". 2336: 2264: 2244: 2221: 2201: 2181: 2157: 2137: 2105: 2070: 2040: 1986: 1951: 1913: 1872: 1852: 1789: 1733: 1713: 1693: 1673: 1653: 1633: 1613: 1585: 1565: 1511: 1487: 1458: 1432: 1408: 1380: 1333: 1313: 1269: 1249: 1195: 1145: 1097: 1063: 1043: 1023: 1003: 983: 953: 919: 896: 876: 856: 836: 810: 784: 761: 741: 721: 701: 649: 626: 606: 586: 566: 534: 482: 462: 442: 419: 390: 370: 350: 318: 298: 278: 246: 217: 197: 177: 157: 137: 105: 1031:; to solve it requires a method to solve problem 2359:0). This use of 0 = 1 validates the 2348:(and the Peano axiom is rewritten 0 =  1079:The identity function is a proof of the formula 1566:{\displaystyle (P\wedge (P\to \bot ))\to \bot } 1250:{\displaystyle (P\wedge (P\to \bot ))\to \bot } 1196:{\displaystyle (P\wedge (P\to \bot ))\to \bot } 931:(nontermination in some programming languages). 2169:. The BHK interpretation instead takes "not" 8: 1766: 1754: 561: 549: 345: 333: 273: 261: 132: 120: 1790:{\displaystyle f(\langle a,b\rangle )=b(a)} 2512:"The Development of Intuitionistic Logic" 2493: 2453: 2425:between natural deduction and functions. 2386:theory identifies the functions with the 2329: 2257: 2234: 2214: 2194: 2174: 2150: 2130: 2083: 2057: 2027: 1964: 1926: 1891: 1865: 1815: 1746: 1726: 1706: 1686: 1666: 1646: 1626: 1606: 1578: 1528: 1504: 1474: 1445: 1425: 1401: 1349: 1326: 1282: 1262: 1212: 1158: 1120: 1084: 1056: 1036: 1016: 996: 970: 940: 912: 889: 869: 849: 823: 800: 774: 754: 734: 714: 676: 665: 639: 619: 599: 579: 547: 509: 498: 475: 455: 435: 406: 383: 363: 331: 311: 291: 259: 233: 210: 190: 170: 150: 118: 92: 33:Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation 18:Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov interpretation 2446: 1853:{\displaystyle (P\wedge (P\to Q))\to Q} 1661:is a function that converts a proof of 1495:is a function that converts a proof of 2121:It is not, in general, possible for a 1381:{\displaystyle (P\wedge (P\to \bot ))} 1314:{\displaystyle (P\wedge (P\to \bot ))} 702:{\displaystyle (\forall x{\in }S)(Px)} 535:{\displaystyle (\exists x{\in }S)(Px)} 1146:{\displaystyle \neg (P\wedge \neg P)} 59:, because of the connection with the 7: 2252:is a function converting a proof of 2145:exactly when there isn't a proof of 1523:Putting it all together, a proof of 2521:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2406:is simply the trivial algorithm if 567:{\displaystyle \langle x,a\rangle } 351:{\displaystyle \langle 1,b\rangle } 279:{\displaystyle \langle 0,a\rangle } 138:{\displaystyle \langle a,b\rangle } 2410:evaluates to the same number that 2331: 2236: 2216: 2094: 2065: 2035: 1975: 1952:{\displaystyle P\vee (P\to \bot )} 1943: 1902: 1708: 1688: 1560: 1548: 1506: 1482: 1453: 1369: 1328: 1302: 1244: 1232: 1190: 1178: 1134: 1122: 914: 891: 831: 802: 670: 503: 55:. It is also sometimes called the 25: 844:, so a proof of it is a function 2209:leads to absurdity, designated 2167:Gödel's incompleteness theorems 2510:Van Atten, Mark (4 May 2022). 2106:{\displaystyle P\vee (\neg P)} 2100: 2091: 2062: 2032: 1987:{\displaystyle P\vee (\neg P)} 1981: 1972: 1946: 1940: 1934: 1914:{\displaystyle P\vee (\neg P)} 1908: 1899: 1844: 1841: 1838: 1832: 1826: 1817: 1784: 1778: 1769: 1751: 1557: 1554: 1551: 1545: 1539: 1530: 1479: 1450: 1375: 1372: 1366: 1360: 1351: 1308: 1305: 1299: 1293: 1284: 1241: 1238: 1235: 1229: 1223: 1214: 1187: 1184: 1181: 1175: 1169: 1160: 1140: 1125: 1089: 975: 828: 696: 687: 684: 667: 529: 520: 517: 500: 411: 1: 2539:Dependently typed programming 2549:Constructivism (mathematics) 2379:will diverge on this point. 2078:is provable then neither is 1051:given a solution to problem 57:realizability interpretation 2435:Curry–Howard correspondence 2286:, then 1 would be equal to 2272:into a proof of absurdity. 991:is the problem of reducing 2565: 2071:{\displaystyle P\to \bot } 2041:{\displaystyle P\to \bot } 1488:{\displaystyle P\to \bot } 1459:{\displaystyle P\to \bot } 837:{\displaystyle P\to \bot } 81:induction on the structure 1593:that converts a pair < 1277:that converts a proof of 864:that converts a proof of 729:that converts an element 450:that converts a proof of 106:{\displaystyle P\wedge Q} 1388:is a pair of proofs < 1114:law of non-contradiction 2245:{\displaystyle \lnot P} 2117:Definition of absurdity 1883:On the other hand, the 247:{\displaystyle P\vee Q} 79:. This is specified by 51:, and independently by 2544:Functional programming 2367:Definition of function 2361:principle of explosion 2355:→ 0 =  2338: 2277:mathematical induction 2266: 2246: 2223: 2203: 2183: 2159: 2139: 2107: 2072: 2042: 1988: 1953: 1915: 1885:law of excluded middle 1874: 1854: 1791: 1741:that does this, where 1735: 1721:. There is a function 1715: 1695: 1675: 1655: 1635: 1615: 1587: 1567: 1513: 1489: 1460: 1434: 1410: 1382: 1335: 1315: 1271: 1251: 1197: 1147: 1099: 1098:{\displaystyle P\to P} 1065: 1045: 1025: 1005: 985: 984:{\displaystyle P\to Q} 955: 921: 898: 878: 858: 838: 812: 811:{\displaystyle \neg P} 786: 763: 743: 723: 703: 651: 628: 608: 588: 568: 536: 484: 464: 444: 421: 420:{\displaystyle P\to Q} 392: 372: 352: 320: 300: 280: 248: 219: 199: 179: 159: 139: 107: 2339: 2337:{\displaystyle \bot } 2267: 2247: 2229:, so that a proof of 2224: 2222:{\displaystyle \bot } 2204: 2184: 2160: 2140: 2108: 2073: 2043: 1989: 1954: 1916: 1875: 1855: 1792: 1736: 1716: 1714:{\displaystyle \bot } 1696: 1694:{\displaystyle \bot } 1676: 1656: 1636: 1616: 1588: 1568: 1514: 1512:{\displaystyle \bot } 1490: 1461: 1435: 1411: 1383: 1336: 1334:{\displaystyle \bot } 1316: 1272: 1252: 1198: 1148: 1100: 1066: 1046: 1026: 1006: 986: 956: 922: 920:{\displaystyle \bot } 907:There is no proof of 899: 897:{\displaystyle \bot } 879: 859: 839: 813: 787: 764: 744: 724: 704: 652: 629: 609: 589: 569: 537: 485: 465: 445: 422: 393: 373: 353: 321: 301: 281: 249: 220: 200: 180: 160: 140: 108: 2388:computable functions 2328: 2256: 2233: 2213: 2193: 2173: 2149: 2129: 2082: 2056: 2026: 1963: 1925: 1890: 1880:is any proposition. 1864: 1814: 1745: 1725: 1705: 1685: 1665: 1645: 1625: 1605: 1577: 1527: 1503: 1473: 1444: 1424: 1400: 1348: 1325: 1281: 1261: 1211: 1157: 1119: 1083: 1055: 1035: 1015: 995: 969: 939: 911: 888: 868: 848: 822: 799: 773: 753: 733: 713: 664: 638: 618: 598: 578: 546: 497: 474: 454: 434: 405: 382: 362: 330: 310: 290: 258: 232: 209: 189: 169: 149: 117: 91: 41:intuitionistic logic 954:{\displaystyle x=y} 927:, the absurdity or 2346:Heyting arithmetic 2334: 2290: + 1, ( 2262: 2242: 2219: 2199: 2179: 2155: 2135: 2103: 2068: 2048:. Thus if neither 2038: 1984: 1949: 1911: 1870: 1850: 1787: 1731: 1711: 1701:– into a proof of 1691: 1671: 1651: 1631: 1611: 1583: 1563: 1509: 1485: 1456: 1430: 1406: 1378: 1331: 1311: 1267: 1247: 1193: 1143: 1095: 1061: 1041: 1021: 1001: 981: 951: 917: 894: 874: 854: 834: 808: 785:{\displaystyle Px} 782: 759: 739: 719: 699: 650:{\displaystyle Px} 647: 624: 604: 584: 564: 532: 480: 460: 440: 417: 388: 368: 348: 316: 296: 276: 244: 215: 195: 175: 155: 135: 103: 71:The interpretation 37:BHK interpretation 29:mathematical logic 2265:{\displaystyle P} 2202:{\displaystyle P} 2182:{\displaystyle P} 2158:{\displaystyle P} 2138:{\displaystyle P} 1873:{\displaystyle Q} 1734:{\displaystyle f} 1674:{\displaystyle P} 1654:{\displaystyle b} 1634:{\displaystyle P} 1614:{\displaystyle a} 1586:{\displaystyle f} 1433:{\displaystyle b} 1409:{\displaystyle a} 1270:{\displaystyle f} 1105:, no matter what 1064:{\displaystyle P} 1044:{\displaystyle Q} 1024:{\displaystyle P} 1004:{\displaystyle Q} 877:{\displaystyle P} 857:{\displaystyle f} 762:{\displaystyle S} 742:{\displaystyle x} 722:{\displaystyle f} 627:{\displaystyle a} 607:{\displaystyle S} 594:is an element of 587:{\displaystyle x} 483:{\displaystyle Q} 463:{\displaystyle P} 443:{\displaystyle f} 391:{\displaystyle Q} 371:{\displaystyle b} 319:{\displaystyle P} 299:{\displaystyle a} 218:{\displaystyle Q} 198:{\displaystyle b} 178:{\displaystyle P} 158:{\displaystyle a} 83:of that formula: 53:Andrey Kolmogorov 16:(Redirected from 2556: 2525: 2516:Zalta, Edward N. 2499: 2497: 2481: 2479: 2457: 2451: 2343: 2341: 2340: 2335: 2271: 2269: 2268: 2263: 2251: 2249: 2248: 2243: 2228: 2226: 2225: 2220: 2208: 2206: 2205: 2200: 2188: 2186: 2185: 2180: 2164: 2162: 2161: 2156: 2144: 2142: 2141: 2136: 2112: 2110: 2109: 2104: 2077: 2075: 2074: 2069: 2047: 2045: 2044: 2039: 1993: 1991: 1990: 1985: 1958: 1956: 1955: 1950: 1920: 1918: 1917: 1912: 1879: 1877: 1876: 1871: 1859: 1857: 1856: 1851: 1796: 1794: 1793: 1788: 1740: 1738: 1737: 1732: 1720: 1718: 1717: 1712: 1700: 1698: 1697: 1692: 1681:into a proof of 1680: 1678: 1677: 1672: 1660: 1658: 1657: 1652: 1640: 1638: 1637: 1632: 1620: 1618: 1617: 1612: 1592: 1590: 1589: 1584: 1572: 1570: 1569: 1564: 1518: 1516: 1515: 1510: 1499:into a proof of 1494: 1492: 1491: 1486: 1465: 1463: 1462: 1457: 1439: 1437: 1436: 1431: 1415: 1413: 1412: 1407: 1387: 1385: 1384: 1379: 1340: 1338: 1337: 1332: 1321:into a proof of 1320: 1318: 1317: 1312: 1276: 1274: 1273: 1268: 1256: 1254: 1253: 1248: 1202: 1200: 1199: 1194: 1152: 1150: 1149: 1144: 1104: 1102: 1101: 1096: 1070: 1068: 1067: 1062: 1050: 1048: 1047: 1042: 1030: 1028: 1027: 1022: 1010: 1008: 1007: 1002: 990: 988: 987: 982: 960: 958: 957: 952: 926: 924: 923: 918: 903: 901: 900: 895: 884:into a proof of 883: 881: 880: 875: 863: 861: 860: 855: 843: 841: 840: 835: 817: 815: 814: 809: 791: 789: 788: 783: 769:into a proof of 768: 766: 765: 760: 748: 746: 745: 740: 728: 726: 725: 720: 708: 706: 705: 700: 680: 656: 654: 653: 648: 633: 631: 630: 625: 613: 611: 610: 605: 593: 591: 590: 585: 573: 571: 570: 565: 541: 539: 538: 533: 513: 489: 487: 486: 481: 470:into a proof of 469: 467: 466: 461: 449: 447: 446: 441: 430: 426: 424: 423: 418: 397: 395: 394: 389: 377: 375: 374: 369: 357: 355: 354: 349: 325: 323: 322: 317: 305: 303: 302: 297: 285: 283: 282: 277: 253: 251: 250: 245: 224: 222: 221: 216: 204: 202: 201: 196: 184: 182: 181: 176: 164: 162: 161: 156: 144: 142: 141: 136: 112: 110: 109: 104: 45:L. E. J. Brouwer 43:was proposed by 21: 2564: 2563: 2559: 2558: 2557: 2555: 2554: 2553: 2529: 2528: 2509: 2506: 2484: 2477: 2469: 2466: 2461: 2460: 2452: 2448: 2443: 2431: 2419:lambda calculus 2369: 2326: 2325: 2308:if and only if 2254: 2253: 2231: 2230: 2211: 2210: 2191: 2190: 2171: 2170: 2147: 2146: 2127: 2126: 2119: 2080: 2079: 2054: 2053: 2024: 2023: 1961: 1960: 1923: 1922: 1888: 1887: 1862: 1861: 1860:as well, where 1812: 1811: 1743: 1742: 1723: 1722: 1703: 1702: 1683: 1682: 1663: 1662: 1643: 1642: 1623: 1622: 1603: 1602: 1575: 1574: 1525: 1524: 1501: 1500: 1471: 1470: 1442: 1441: 1422: 1421: 1398: 1397: 1346: 1345: 1323: 1322: 1279: 1278: 1259: 1258: 1209: 1208: 1155: 1154: 1117: 1116: 1081: 1080: 1077: 1053: 1052: 1033: 1032: 1013: 1012: 993: 992: 967: 966: 937: 936: 909: 908: 886: 885: 866: 865: 846: 845: 820: 819: 797: 796: 771: 770: 751: 750: 731: 730: 711: 710: 662: 661: 636: 635: 616: 615: 596: 595: 576: 575: 544: 543: 495: 494: 472: 471: 452: 451: 432: 431: 428: 403: 402: 380: 379: 360: 359: 328: 327: 308: 307: 288: 287: 256: 255: 230: 229: 207: 206: 187: 186: 167: 166: 147: 146: 115: 114: 89: 88: 73: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 2562: 2560: 2552: 2551: 2546: 2541: 2531: 2530: 2527: 2526: 2505: 2502: 2501: 2500: 2495:10.1.1.10.6972 2482: 2465: 2462: 2459: 2458: 2454:Van Atten 2022 2445: 2444: 2442: 2439: 2438: 2437: 2430: 2427: 2423:correspondence 2377:constructivism 2368: 2365: 2333: 2281:natural number 2261: 2241: 2238: 2218: 2198: 2178: 2154: 2134: 2123:logical system 2118: 2115: 2102: 2099: 2096: 2093: 2090: 2087: 2067: 2064: 2061: 2037: 2034: 2031: 2022:is a proof of 2010:is a proof of 1994:is a pair < 1983: 1980: 1977: 1974: 1971: 1968: 1948: 1945: 1942: 1939: 1936: 1933: 1930: 1910: 1907: 1904: 1901: 1898: 1895: 1869: 1849: 1846: 1843: 1840: 1837: 1834: 1831: 1828: 1825: 1822: 1819: 1786: 1783: 1780: 1777: 1774: 1771: 1768: 1765: 1762: 1759: 1756: 1753: 1750: 1730: 1710: 1690: 1670: 1650: 1630: 1621:is a proof of 1610: 1582: 1573:is a function 1562: 1559: 1556: 1553: 1550: 1547: 1544: 1541: 1538: 1535: 1532: 1521: 1520: 1508: 1484: 1481: 1478: 1467: 1455: 1452: 1449: 1440:is a proof of 1429: 1416:is a proof of 1405: 1377: 1374: 1371: 1368: 1365: 1362: 1359: 1356: 1353: 1342: 1330: 1310: 1307: 1304: 1301: 1298: 1295: 1292: 1289: 1286: 1266: 1257:is a function 1246: 1243: 1240: 1237: 1234: 1231: 1228: 1225: 1222: 1219: 1216: 1192: 1189: 1186: 1183: 1180: 1177: 1174: 1171: 1168: 1165: 1162: 1142: 1139: 1136: 1133: 1130: 1127: 1124: 1094: 1091: 1088: 1076: 1073: 1060: 1040: 1020: 1000: 980: 977: 974: 950: 947: 944: 933: 932: 916: 905: 893: 873: 853: 833: 830: 827: 818:is defined as 807: 804: 793: 781: 778: 758: 738: 718: 709:is a function 698: 695: 692: 689: 686: 683: 679: 675: 672: 669: 658: 646: 643: 634:is a proof of 623: 603: 583: 563: 560: 557: 554: 551: 531: 528: 525: 522: 519: 516: 512: 508: 505: 502: 491: 479: 459: 439: 416: 413: 410: 399: 387: 378:is a proof of 367: 347: 344: 341: 338: 335: 315: 306:is a proof of 295: 275: 272: 269: 266: 263: 243: 240: 237: 226: 214: 205:is a proof of 194: 174: 165:is a proof of 154: 134: 131: 128: 125: 122: 102: 99: 96: 72: 69: 65:Stephen Kleene 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 2561: 2550: 2547: 2545: 2542: 2540: 2537: 2536: 2534: 2523: 2522: 2517: 2513: 2508: 2507: 2504:External link 2503: 2496: 2491: 2487: 2486:Troelstra, A. 2483: 2476: 2472: 2471:Troelstra, A. 2468: 2467: 2463: 2455: 2450: 2447: 2440: 2436: 2433: 2432: 2428: 2426: 2424: 2420: 2417:If one takes 2415: 2413: 2409: 2405: 2401: 2398:. A proof of 2397: 2393: 2389: 2385: 2384:realizability 2380: 2378: 2374: 2366: 2364: 2362: 2358: 2354: 2351: 2347: 2321: 2319: 2315: 2311: 2307: 2304: 2301: =  2300: 2297: 2293: 2289: 2285: 2282: 2278: 2273: 2259: 2239: 2196: 2189:to mean that 2176: 2168: 2152: 2132: 2124: 2116: 2114: 2097: 2088: 2085: 2059: 2051: 2029: 2021: 2017: 2013: 2009: 2005: 2001: 1997: 1978: 1969: 1966: 1937: 1931: 1928: 1905: 1896: 1893: 1886: 1881: 1867: 1847: 1835: 1829: 1823: 1820: 1809: 1808: 1802: 1800: 1781: 1775: 1772: 1763: 1760: 1757: 1748: 1728: 1668: 1648: 1628: 1608: 1601:> – where 1600: 1596: 1580: 1542: 1536: 1533: 1498: 1476: 1468: 1447: 1427: 1419: 1403: 1395: 1391: 1363: 1357: 1354: 1343: 1296: 1290: 1287: 1264: 1226: 1220: 1217: 1206: 1205: 1204: 1172: 1166: 1163: 1137: 1131: 1128: 1115: 1110: 1108: 1092: 1086: 1074: 1072: 1058: 1038: 1018: 998: 978: 972: 962: 948: 945: 942: 930: 906: 871: 851: 825: 805: 794: 779: 776: 756: 736: 716: 693: 690: 681: 677: 673: 659: 644: 641: 621: 601: 581: 558: 555: 552: 526: 523: 514: 510: 506: 492: 477: 457: 437: 414: 408: 400: 385: 365: 342: 339: 336: 313: 293: 270: 267: 264: 241: 238: 235: 227: 212: 192: 172: 152: 129: 126: 123: 100: 97: 94: 86: 85: 84: 82: 78: 70: 68: 66: 62: 61:realizability 58: 54: 50: 49:Arend Heyting 46: 42: 38: 34: 30: 19: 2519: 2449: 2416: 2411: 2407: 2403: 2399: 2395: 2391: 2381: 2372: 2370: 2356: 2352: 2349: 2322: 2317: 2313: 2309: 2305: 2302: 2298: 2295: 2287: 2283: 2274: 2120: 2049: 2019: 2015: 2011: 2007: 2003: 1999: 1995: 1882: 1807:modus ponens 1805: 1803: 1798: 1598: 1594: 1522: 1496: 1417: 1396:>, where 1393: 1389: 1111: 1106: 1078: 963: 934: 795:The formula 74: 56: 36: 32: 26: 2292:Peano axiom 2002:> where 1921:expands to 1469:A proof of 1344:A proof of 1207:A proof of 1153:expands to 929:bottom type 660:A proof of 493:A proof of 401:A proof of 228:A proof of 87:A proof of 2533:Categories 2464:References 542:is a pair 254:is either 113:is a pair 63:theory of 2490:CiteSeerX 2382:Kleene's 2332:⊥ 2237:¬ 2217:⊥ 2095:¬ 2089:∨ 2066:⊥ 2063:→ 2036:⊥ 2033:→ 2018:is 1 and 2006:is 0 and 1976:¬ 1970:∨ 1944:⊥ 1941:→ 1932:∨ 1903:¬ 1897:∨ 1845:→ 1833:→ 1824:∧ 1767:⟩ 1755:⟨ 1709:⊥ 1689:⊥ 1561:⊥ 1558:→ 1549:⊥ 1546:→ 1537:∧ 1507:⊥ 1483:⊥ 1480:→ 1454:⊥ 1451:→ 1370:⊥ 1367:→ 1358:∧ 1329:⊥ 1303:⊥ 1300:→ 1291:∧ 1245:⊥ 1242:→ 1233:⊥ 1230:→ 1221:∧ 1191:⊥ 1188:→ 1179:⊥ 1176:→ 1167:∧ 1135:¬ 1132:∧ 1123:¬ 1090:→ 976:→ 915:⊥ 892:⊥ 832:⊥ 829:→ 803:¬ 678:∈ 671:∀ 562:⟩ 550:⟨ 511:∈ 504:∃ 412:→ 346:⟩ 334:⟨ 274:⟩ 262:⟨ 239:∨ 133:⟩ 121:⟨ 98:∧ 2473:(1991). 2429:See also 2373:function 1998:,  1597:,  1392:,  1075:Examples 429:function 2518:(ed.). 77:formula 2492:  2165:; see 1641:, and 1420:, and 574:where 358:where 286:where 145:where 31:, the 2514:. In 2478:(PDF) 2441:Notes 2014:, or 1810:rule 427:is a 39:, of 35:, or 2052:nor 1801:is. 1112:The 1109:is. 614:and 185:and 47:and 2344:in 1011:to 749:of 326:or 27:In 2535:: 2402:= 2394:= 2363:. 2312:= 2294:: 2113:. 1203:: 1071:. 2524:. 2498:. 2480:. 2456:. 2412:y 2408:x 2404:y 2400:x 2396:y 2392:x 2357:S 2353:n 2350:S 2318:n 2314:n 2310:m 2306:n 2303:S 2299:m 2296:S 2288:n 2284:n 2260:P 2240:P 2197:P 2177:P 2153:P 2133:P 2101:) 2098:P 2092:( 2086:P 2060:P 2050:P 2030:P 2020:b 2016:a 2012:P 2008:b 2004:a 2000:b 1996:a 1982:) 1979:P 1973:( 1967:P 1947:) 1938:P 1935:( 1929:P 1909:) 1906:P 1900:( 1894:P 1868:Q 1848:Q 1842:) 1839:) 1836:Q 1830:P 1827:( 1821:P 1818:( 1799:P 1785:) 1782:a 1779:( 1776:b 1773:= 1770:) 1764:b 1761:, 1758:a 1752:( 1749:f 1729:f 1669:P 1649:b 1629:P 1609:a 1599:b 1595:a 1581:f 1555:) 1552:) 1543:P 1540:( 1534:P 1531:( 1519:. 1497:P 1477:P 1466:. 1448:P 1428:b 1418:P 1404:a 1394:b 1390:a 1376:) 1373:) 1364:P 1361:( 1355:P 1352:( 1341:. 1309:) 1306:) 1297:P 1294:( 1288:P 1285:( 1265:f 1239:) 1236:) 1227:P 1224:( 1218:P 1215:( 1185:) 1182:) 1173:P 1170:( 1164:P 1161:( 1141:) 1138:P 1129:P 1126:( 1107:P 1093:P 1087:P 1059:P 1039:Q 1019:P 999:Q 979:Q 973:P 949:y 946:= 943:x 904:. 872:P 852:f 826:P 806:P 792:. 780:x 777:P 757:S 737:x 717:f 697:) 694:x 691:P 688:( 685:) 682:S 674:x 668:( 657:. 645:x 642:P 622:a 602:S 582:x 559:a 556:, 553:x 530:) 527:x 524:P 521:( 518:) 515:S 507:x 501:( 490:. 478:Q 458:P 438:f 415:Q 409:P 398:. 386:Q 366:b 343:b 340:, 337:1 314:P 294:a 271:a 268:, 265:0 242:Q 236:P 225:. 213:Q 193:b 173:P 153:a 130:b 127:, 124:a 101:Q 95:P 20:)

Index

Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov interpretation
mathematical logic
intuitionistic logic
L. E. J. Brouwer
Arend Heyting
Andrey Kolmogorov
realizability
Stephen Kleene
formula
induction on the structure
bottom type
law of non-contradiction
modus ponens
law of excluded middle
logical system
Gödel's incompleteness theorems
mathematical induction
natural number
Peano axiom
Heyting arithmetic
principle of explosion
constructivism
realizability
computable functions
lambda calculus
correspondence
Curry–Howard correspondence
Van Atten 2022
Troelstra, A.
"History of Constructivism in the Twentieth Century"

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.