Knowledge

Counterexample

Source 📝

106:, or she can attempt to find a counterexample of the statement if she suspects it to be false. In the latter case, a counterexample would be a rectangle that is not a square, such as a rectangle with two sides of length 5 and two sides of length 7. However, despite having found rectangles that were not squares, all the rectangles she did find had four sides. She then makes the new conjecture "All rectangles have four sides". This is logically weaker than her original conjecture, since every square has four sides, but not every four-sided shape is a square. 114:. For example, suppose that after a while, the mathematician above settled on the new conjecture "All shapes that are rectangles and have four sides of equal length are squares". This conjecture has two parts to the hypothesis: the shape must be 'a rectangle' and must have 'four sides of equal length'. The mathematician then would like to know if she can remove either assumption, and still maintain the truth of her conjecture. This means that she needs to check the truth of the following two statements: 651: 155:" is the number 2, as it is a prime number but is not an odd number. Neither of the numbers 7 or 10 is a counterexample, as neither of them are enough to contradict the statement. In this example, 2 is in fact the only possible counterexample to the statement, even though that alone is enough to contradict the statement. In a similar manner, the statement "All 272:, counterexamples are usually used to argue that a certain philosophical position is wrong by showing that it does not apply in certain cases. Alternatively, the first philosopher can modify their claim so that the counterexample no longer applies; this is analogous to when a mathematician modifies a conjecture because of a counterexample. 303:
Callicles might challenge Socrates' counterexample, arguing perhaps that the common rabble really are better than the nobles, or that even in their large numbers, they still are not stronger. But if Callicles accepts the counterexample, then he must either withdraw his claim, or modify it so that the
66:
In mathematics, counterexamples are often used to prove the boundaries of possible theorems. By using counterexamples to show that certain conjectures are false, mathematical researchers can then avoid going down blind alleys and learn to modify conjectures to produce provable theorems. It is
109:
The above example explained — in a simplified way — how a mathematician might weaken her conjecture in the face of counterexamples, but counterexamples can also be used to demonstrate the necessity of certain assumptions and
304:
counterexample no longer applies. For example, he might modify his claim to refer only to individual persons, requiring him to think of the common people as a collection of individuals rather than as a mob.
300:
of worse character. Thus Socrates has proposed a counterexample to Callicles' claim, by looking in an area that Callicles perhaps did not expect — groups of people rather than individual persons.
54:. For example, the fact that "student John Smith is not lazy" is a counterexample to the generalization "students are lazy", and both a counterexample to, and disproof of, the 565: 296:
replies that, because of their strength of numbers, the class of common rabble is stronger than the propertied class of nobles, even though the masses are
307:
As it happens, he modifies his claim to say "wiser" instead of "stronger", arguing that no amount of numerical superiority can make people wiser.
533: 681: 474: 170: 671: 636: 621: 604: 589: 574: 557: 423: 289:, trying to define what it means to say that some people are "better" than others, claims that those who are stronger are better. 199: 249: 612: 516: 321: 655: 521: 67:
sometimes said that mathematical development consists primarily in finding (and proving) theorems and counterexamples.
548: 138: 218: 686: 55: 543: 507: 326: 142: 253: 152: 245: 103: 398: 281: 241: 99: 632: 617: 600: 585: 570: 553: 539: 529: 512: 448: 92: 125:
A counterexample to (1) was already given above, and a counterexample to (2) is a non-square
438: 257: 226: 164: 234: 676: 211: 203: 156: 35: 665: 316: 230: 207: 443: 129:. Thus, the mathematician now knows that each assumption by itself is insufficient. 502: 374: 160: 148: 599:. Corrected reprint of the second (1965) edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY 349: 297: 47: 17: 269: 184:
power. This conjecture was disproved in 1966, with a counterexample involving
111: 95:", and she is interested in knowing whether this statement is true or false. 88: 84: 51: 452: 167:" has the number 1 as a counterexample, as 1 is neither prime nor composite. 650: 286: 293: 76: 126: 276: 80: 43: 39: 222: 192: = 5 counterexamples are now known, as well as some 121:"All shapes that have four sides of equal length are squares". 424:"Counterexample to Euler's conjecture on sums of like powers" 173:
was disproved by counterexample. It asserted that at least
83:, and she wishes to prove certain theorems about them. She 42:
a counterexample disproves the generalization, and does so
582:Counterexamples in Probability and Real Analysis 627:Michael Copobianco & John Mulluzzo (1978) 595:Bernard R. Gelbaum, John M. H. Olmsted (2003) 566:Counterexamples in Probability and Statistics 563:Joseph P. Romano and Andrew F. Siegel (1986) 431:Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 118:"All shapes that are rectangles are squares." 8: 629:Examples and Counterexamples in Graph Theory 240:Other examples include the disproofs of the 214:imply optimal control laws that are linear. 437:(6). Americal Mathematical Society: 1079. 210:and a linear equation of evolution of the 442: 75:Suppose that a mathematician is studying 180:powers were necessary to sum to another 98:In this case, she can either attempt to 338: 147:A counterexample to the statement "all 202:shows that it is not always true (for 580:Gary L. Wise and Eric B. Hall (1993) 569:Chapman & Hall, New York, London 526:Proof in Mathematics: An Introduction 229:is false as shown by counterexamples 7: 584:. Oxford University Press, New York 344: 342: 27:Exception to a proposed general rule 616:Second edition, Wiley, Chichester 511:(1976) Cambridge University Press 25: 102:the truth of the statement using 649: 196: = 4 counterexamples. 171:Euler's sum of powers conjecture 444:10.1090/s0002-9904-1966-11654-3 613:Counterexamples in Probability 322:Exception that proves the rule 1: 473:Elkies, Noam (October 1988). 200:Witsenhausen's counterexample 250:Hilbert's fourteenth problem 682:Interpretation (philosophy) 597:Counterexamples in Analysis 549:Counterexamples in Topology 350:"Mathwords: Counterexample" 221:are mappings that preserve 139:Counterexamples in topology 133:Other mathematical examples 703: 610:Jordan M. Stoyanov (1997) 482:Mathematics of Computation 219:Euclidean plane isometries 136: 631:, Elsevier North-Holland 399:"What Is Counterexample?" 58:"all students are lazy." 672:Mathematical terminology 524:and Albert Daoud (2011) 56:universal quantification 422:Lander, Parkin (1966). 654:Quotations related to 544:J. Arthur Seebach, Jr. 508:Proofs and Refutations 475:"On A4 + B4 + C4 = D4" 327:Minimal counterexample 188: = 5; other 143:Minimal counterexample 34:is any exception to a 552:, Springer, New York 379:mathworld.wolfram.com 403:www.cut-the-knot.org 248:, the conjecture of 373:Weisstein, Eric W. 206:) that a quadratic 104:deductive reasoning 242:Seifert conjecture 540:Lynn Arthur Steen 534:978-0-646-54509-7 354:www.mathwords.com 254:Tait's conjecture 71:Rectangle example 46:in the fields of 16:(Redirected from 694: 687:Methods of proof 653: 490: 489: 479: 470: 464: 463: 461: 459: 446: 428: 419: 413: 412: 410: 409: 395: 389: 388: 386: 385: 375:"Counterexample" 370: 364: 363: 361: 360: 346: 275:For example, in 258:Ganea conjecture 246:Pólya conjecture 204:control problems 21: 702: 701: 697: 696: 695: 693: 692: 691: 662: 661: 646: 499: 497:Further reading 494: 493: 488:(184): 825–835. 477: 472: 471: 467: 457: 455: 426: 421: 420: 416: 407: 405: 397: 396: 392: 383: 381: 372: 371: 367: 358: 356: 348: 347: 340: 335: 313: 266: 235:squeeze mapping 157:natural numbers 145: 135: 73: 64: 28: 23: 22: 18:Counterexamples 15: 12: 11: 5: 700: 698: 690: 689: 684: 679: 674: 664: 663: 660: 659: 656:Counterexample 645: 644:External links 642: 641: 640: 625: 608: 593: 578: 561: 537: 528:, Kew, Sydney 522:James Franklin 519: 498: 495: 492: 491: 465: 414: 390: 365: 337: 336: 334: 331: 330: 329: 324: 319: 312: 309: 265: 262: 212:state variable 134: 131: 123: 122: 119: 72: 69: 63: 62:In mathematics 60: 36:generalization 32:counterexample 26: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 699: 688: 685: 683: 680: 678: 675: 673: 670: 669: 667: 657: 652: 648: 647: 643: 638: 637:0-444-00255-3 634: 630: 626: 623: 622:0-471-96538-3 619: 615: 614: 609: 606: 605:0-486-42875-3 602: 598: 594: 591: 590:0-19-507068-2 587: 583: 579: 576: 575:0-412-98901-8 572: 568: 567: 562: 559: 558:0-486-68735-X 555: 551: 550: 545: 541: 538: 535: 531: 527: 523: 520: 518: 514: 510: 509: 504: 501: 500: 496: 487: 483: 476: 469: 466: 454: 450: 445: 440: 436: 432: 425: 418: 415: 404: 400: 394: 391: 380: 376: 369: 366: 355: 351: 345: 343: 339: 332: 328: 325: 323: 320: 318: 317:Contradiction 315: 314: 310: 308: 305: 301: 299: 295: 290: 288: 284: 283: 278: 273: 271: 264:In philosophy 263: 261: 259: 255: 251: 247: 243: 238: 236: 232: 231:shear mapping 228: 224: 220: 215: 213: 209: 208:loss function 205: 201: 197: 195: 191: 187: 183: 179: 176: 172: 168: 166: 162: 158: 154: 150: 149:prime numbers 144: 140: 132: 130: 128: 120: 117: 116: 115: 113: 107: 105: 101: 96: 94: 90: 86: 82: 78: 70: 68: 61: 59: 57: 53: 49: 45: 41: 37: 33: 19: 658:at Wikiquote 628: 611: 596: 581: 564: 547: 525: 506: 503:Imre Lakatos 485: 481: 468: 456:. Retrieved 434: 430: 417: 406:. Retrieved 402: 393: 382:. Retrieved 378: 368: 357:. Retrieved 353: 306: 302: 291: 280: 274: 267: 239: 216: 198: 193: 189: 185: 181: 177: 174: 169: 146: 124: 108: 97: 74: 65: 31: 29: 298:prima facie 159:are either 153:odd numbers 85:conjectures 48:mathematics 666:Categories 517:0521290384 408:2019-11-28 384:2019-11-28 359:2019-11-28 333:References 270:philosophy 256:, and the 225:, but the 137:See also: 112:hypothesis 89:rectangles 87:that "All 52:philosophy 44:rigorously 453:0273-0979 287:Callicles 165:composite 536:, ch. 6. 458:2 August 311:See also 294:Socrates 227:converse 77:geometry 546:(1978) 282:Gorgias 127:rhombus 93:squares 635:  620:  603:  588:  573:  556:  532:  515:  451:  244:, the 81:shapes 38:. In 677:Logic 478:(PDF) 427:(PDF) 277:Plato 161:prime 100:prove 40:logic 633:ISBN 618:ISBN 601:ISBN 586:ISBN 571:ISBN 554:ISBN 542:and 530:ISBN 513:ISBN 460:2018 449:ISSN 292:But 233:and 223:area 217:All 151:are 141:and 91:are 79:and 50:and 439:doi 279:'s 268:In 163:or 668:: 505:, 486:51 484:. 480:. 447:. 435:72 433:. 429:. 401:. 377:. 352:. 341:^ 285:, 260:. 252:, 237:. 30:A 639:. 624:. 607:. 592:. 577:. 560:. 462:. 441:: 411:. 387:. 362:. 194:n 190:n 186:n 182:n 178:n 175:n 20:)

Index

Counterexamples
generalization
logic
rigorously
mathematics
philosophy
universal quantification
geometry
shapes
conjectures
rectangles
squares
prove
deductive reasoning
hypothesis
rhombus
Counterexamples in topology
Minimal counterexample
prime numbers
odd numbers
natural numbers
prime
composite
Euler's sum of powers conjecture
Witsenhausen's counterexample
control problems
loss function
state variable
Euclidean plane isometries
area

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.