Knowledge

Egalitarian rule

Source đź“ť

514:, any leximin function is Pareto-inefficient for a society that must make tradeoffs under uncertainty: There exist situations in which every person in a society would be better-off (ex ante) if they were to take a particular bet, but the leximin rule will reject it (because some person might be made worse off ex post). 451:
Often, there are many different states with the same minimum utility. For example, a state with utility profile (0,100,100) has the same minimum value as a state with utility profile (0,0,0). In this case, the egalitarian rule often uses the
735: 526:, that is: if utility is "moved" from an agent with more utility to an agent with less utility, and as a result, the utility-difference between them becomes smaller, then resulting alternative is preferred. 442: 246: 762: 572:
represents all possible allocations, and the goal is to find an allocation which maximizes the minimum utility, or the leximin vector. This rule has been studied in several contexts:
311: 539:
Independence of common utility pace - if all utilities are transformed by a common monotonically-increasing function, then the ordering of the alternatives remains the same.
456:, that is: subject to maximizing the smallest utility, it aims to maximize the next-smallest utility; subject to that, maximize the next-smallest utility, and so on. 365: 205: 576: 570: 331: 179: 156: 132: 108: 88: 772: 745: 671: 800: 529:
Moreover, the leximin rule is the only social-welfare ordering rule which simultaneously satisfies the following three properties:
607: 376: 967: 210: 511: 523: 510:
The leximin rule is Pareto-efficient if the outcomes of every decision are known with perfect certainty. However, by
977: 50:) is a rule saying that, among all possible alternatives, society should pick the alternative which maximizes the 624: 588: 972: 629: 618: 582: 90:
be a set of possible `states of the world' or `alternatives'. Society wishes to choose a single state from
858: 613: 111: 270: 334: 263: 31: 653: 459:
For example, suppose there are two individuals - Alice and George, and three possible states: state
135: 35: 943: 896: 870: 716: 935: 888: 839: 796: 768: 741: 708: 667: 17: 927: 880: 829: 700: 659: 475:
is leximin-optimal, since its utility profile is (2,4) which is leximin-larger than that of
344: 184: 610:- a different rule that emphasizes the sum of utilities rather than the smallest utility. 333:
which are `best' for society. The question of what 'best' means is the basic question of
555: 316: 164: 141: 117: 93: 73: 55: 961: 549: 453: 900: 834: 817: 54:
of all individuals in society. It is a formal mathematical representation of the
494: 884: 59: 939: 892: 843: 712: 486:
The egalitarian rule strengthened with the leximin order is often called the
663: 947: 915: 720: 688: 250: 181:
be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each
931: 704: 875: 62:' principle of maximizing the welfare of the worst-off individual. 857:
Nicosia, Gaia; Pacifici, Andrea; Pferschy, Ulrich (2017-03-16).
818:"Computing leximin-optimal solutions in constraint networks" 916:"Individual Monotonicity and Lexicographic Maxmin Solution" 548:
The egalitarian rule is particularly useful as a rule for
471:
gives a utility of 1 to Alice and 8 to George. Then state
371:, that is, it solves the following optimization problem: 689:"Equity and the Informational Basis of Collective Choice" 467:
gives a utility of 9 to Alice and 1 to George; and state
497:
in 1970, and discussed in depth in many later books.
859:"Price of Fairness for allocating a bounded resource" 558: 493:
The leximin rule for social choice was introduced by
463:
gives a utility of 2 to Alice and 4 to George; state
437:{\displaystyle \max _{x\in X}\min _{i\in I}u_{i}(x).} 379: 347: 319: 273: 213: 187: 167: 144: 120: 96: 76: 490:, to distinguish it from the simpler max-min rule. 254:, describing the amount of happiness an individual 241:{\displaystyle u_{i}:X\longrightarrow \mathbb {R} } 816:Bouveret, Sylvain; LemaĂ®tre, Michel (2009-02-01). 564: 436: 359: 325: 305: 240: 199: 173: 150: 126: 102: 82: 397: 381: 8: 687:D'Aspremont, Claude; Gevers, Louis (1977). 134:may represent the set of candidates; in a 874: 833: 621:- max-min fairness in process scheduling. 577:Division of a single homogeneous resource 557: 416: 400: 384: 378: 346: 318: 291: 281: 272: 234: 233: 218: 212: 186: 166: 143: 119: 95: 75: 863:European Journal of Operational Research 786: 784: 158:may represent all possible allocations. 27:Rawlsian decision rule for social choice 795:. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. 641: 764:Axioms of Cooperative Decision Making 7: 793:Fair Division and Collective Welfare 655:Collective Choice and Social Welfare 647: 645: 267:is a mechanism which uses the data 58:philosophy. It also corresponds to 258:derives from each possible state. 25: 597:Egalitarian (leximin) bargaining. 306:{\displaystyle (u_{i})_{i\in I}} 734:Kolm, Serge-Christophe (2002). 544:Egalitarian resource allocation 522:The leximin rule satisfies the 313:to select some element(s) from 767:. Cambridge University Press. 693:The Review of Economic Studies 512:Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem 428: 422: 288: 274: 230: 18:Egalitarian social choice rule 1: 835:10.1016/j.artint.2008.10.010 761:Moulin, Herve (1991-07-26). 658:. Harvard University Press. 594:Egalitarian item allocation. 652:Sen, Amartya (2017-02-20). 552:. In this setting, the set 994: 885:10.1016/j.ejor.2016.08.013 625:Regret (decision theory) 589:Egalitarian cake-cutting 822:Artificial Intelligence 619:Max-min fair scheduling 583:Fair subset sum problem 536:Pigou-Dalton principle; 614:Proportional-fair rule 566: 524:Pigou–Dalton principle 438: 361: 360:{\displaystyle x\in X} 327: 307: 242: 201: 200:{\displaystyle i\in I} 175: 152: 128: 112:single-winner election 104: 84: 791:Herve Moulin (2004). 664:10.4159/9780674974616 567: 518:Pigou-Dalton property 439: 362: 328: 308: 243: 202: 176: 153: 129: 110:. For example, in a 105: 85: 968:Social choice theory 914:Imai, Haruo (1983). 630:Wald's maximin model 556: 377: 367:which maximizes the 345: 335:social choice theory 317: 271: 211: 185: 165: 142: 118: 94: 74: 506:Pareto inefficiency 341:selects an element 136:resource allocation 36:operations research 737:Justice and Equity 562: 533:Pareto efficiency; 434: 411: 395: 357: 323: 303: 264:social choice rule 238: 197: 171: 148: 124: 100: 80: 978:Fairness criteria 774:978-0-521-42458-5 747:978-0-262-61179-4 673:978-0-674-97461-6 565:{\displaystyle X} 396: 380: 326:{\displaystyle X} 174:{\displaystyle I} 151:{\displaystyle X} 127:{\displaystyle X} 103:{\displaystyle X} 83:{\displaystyle X} 42:(also called the 16:(Redirected from 985: 952: 951: 911: 905: 904: 878: 854: 848: 847: 837: 813: 807: 806: 788: 779: 778: 758: 752: 751: 731: 725: 724: 684: 678: 677: 649: 608:Utilitarian rule 571: 569: 568: 563: 443: 441: 440: 435: 421: 420: 410: 394: 366: 364: 363: 358: 339:egalitarian rule 332: 330: 329: 324: 312: 310: 309: 304: 302: 301: 286: 285: 251:utility function 247: 245: 244: 239: 237: 223: 222: 206: 204: 203: 198: 180: 178: 177: 172: 157: 155: 154: 149: 133: 131: 130: 125: 109: 107: 106: 101: 89: 87: 86: 81: 40:egalitarian rule 21: 993: 992: 988: 987: 986: 984: 983: 982: 958: 957: 956: 955: 932:10.2307/1911997 913: 912: 908: 856: 855: 851: 815: 814: 810: 803: 790: 789: 782: 775: 760: 759: 755: 748: 733: 732: 728: 705:10.2307/2297061 686: 685: 681: 674: 651: 650: 643: 638: 604: 554: 553: 546: 520: 508: 503: 449: 444: 412: 375: 374: 369:minimum utility 343: 342: 315: 314: 287: 277: 269: 268: 214: 209: 208: 183: 182: 163: 162: 140: 139: 116: 115: 92: 91: 72: 71: 68: 52:minimum utility 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 991: 989: 981: 980: 975: 973:Egalitarianism 970: 960: 959: 954: 953: 926:(2): 389–401. 906: 869:(3): 933–943. 849: 828:(2): 343–364. 808: 801: 780: 773: 753: 746: 726: 699:(2): 199–209. 679: 672: 640: 639: 637: 634: 633: 632: 627: 622: 616: 611: 603: 600: 599: 598: 595: 592: 586: 580: 561: 545: 542: 541: 540: 537: 534: 519: 516: 507: 504: 502: 499: 448: 445: 433: 430: 427: 424: 419: 415: 409: 406: 403: 399: 393: 390: 387: 383: 373: 356: 353: 350: 322: 300: 297: 294: 290: 284: 280: 276: 236: 232: 229: 226: 221: 217: 196: 193: 190: 170: 147: 123: 99: 79: 67: 64: 26: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 990: 979: 976: 974: 971: 969: 966: 965: 963: 949: 945: 941: 937: 933: 929: 925: 921: 917: 910: 907: 902: 898: 894: 890: 886: 882: 877: 872: 868: 864: 860: 853: 850: 845: 841: 836: 831: 827: 823: 819: 812: 809: 804: 802:9780262134231 798: 794: 787: 785: 781: 776: 770: 766: 765: 757: 754: 749: 743: 740:. MIT Press. 739: 738: 730: 727: 722: 718: 714: 710: 706: 702: 698: 694: 690: 683: 680: 675: 669: 665: 661: 657: 656: 648: 646: 642: 635: 631: 628: 626: 623: 620: 617: 615: 612: 609: 606: 605: 601: 596: 593: 590: 587: 584: 581: 578: 575: 574: 573: 559: 551: 550:fair division 543: 538: 535: 532: 531: 530: 527: 525: 517: 515: 513: 505: 500: 498: 496: 491: 489: 484: 482: 478: 474: 470: 466: 462: 457: 455: 454:leximin order 446: 431: 425: 417: 413: 407: 404: 401: 391: 388: 385: 372: 370: 354: 351: 348: 340: 336: 320: 298: 295: 292: 282: 278: 266: 265: 259: 257: 253: 252: 227: 224: 219: 215: 194: 191: 188: 168: 159: 145: 137: 121: 113: 97: 77: 65: 63: 61: 57: 53: 49: 48:Rawlsian rule 45: 41: 37: 33: 32:social choice 19: 923: 920:Econometrica 919: 909: 866: 862: 852: 825: 821: 811: 792: 763: 756: 736: 729: 696: 692: 682: 654: 547: 528: 521: 509: 492: 488:leximin rule 487: 485: 480: 476: 472: 468: 464: 460: 458: 450: 447:Leximin rule 368: 338: 262: 260: 255: 249: 160: 69: 51: 47: 44:max-min rule 43: 39: 29: 495:Amartya Sen 56:egalitarian 962:Categories 876:1508.05253 636:References 501:Properties 479:(9,1) and 66:Definition 60:John Rawls 940:0012-9682 893:0377-2217 844:0004-3702 713:0034-6527 405:∈ 389:∈ 352:∈ 296:∈ 231:⟶ 192:∈ 138:setting, 901:14229329 602:See also 948:1911997 721:2297061 483:(1,8). 46:or the 946:  938:  899:  891:  842:  799:  771:  744:  719:  711:  670:  337:. The 207:, let 38:, the 944:JSTOR 897:S2CID 871:arXiv 717:JSTOR 248:be a 936:ISSN 889:ISSN 840:ISSN 797:ISBN 769:ISBN 742:ISBN 709:ISSN 668:ISBN 161:Let 70:Let 34:and 928:doi 881:doi 867:257 830:doi 826:173 701:doi 660:doi 398:min 382:max 30:In 964:: 942:. 934:. 924:51 922:. 918:. 895:. 887:. 879:. 865:. 861:. 838:. 824:. 820:. 783:^ 715:. 707:. 697:44 695:. 691:. 666:. 644:^ 261:A 114:, 950:. 930:: 903:. 883:: 873:: 846:. 832:: 805:. 777:. 750:. 723:. 703:: 676:. 662:: 591:; 585:; 579:; 560:X 481:z 477:y 473:x 469:z 465:y 461:x 432:. 429:) 426:x 423:( 418:i 414:u 408:I 402:i 392:X 386:x 355:X 349:x 321:X 299:I 293:i 289:) 283:i 279:u 275:( 256:i 235:R 228:X 225:: 220:i 216:u 195:I 189:i 169:I 146:X 122:X 98:X 78:X 20:)

Index

Egalitarian social choice rule
social choice
operations research
egalitarian
John Rawls
single-winner election
resource allocation
utility function
social choice rule
social choice theory
leximin order
Amartya Sen
Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem
Pigou–Dalton principle
fair division
Division of a single homogeneous resource
Fair subset sum problem
Egalitarian cake-cutting
Utilitarian rule
Proportional-fair rule
Max-min fair scheduling
Regret (decision theory)
Wald's maximin model


Collective Choice and Social Welfare
doi
10.4159/9780674974616
ISBN
978-0-674-97461-6

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑