Knowledge

Eric Heinze

Source 📝

126:, Howe explains how, well into the 20th century, scholars often thought that Shakespeare would not have sought to convey a serious socio-legal critique in a seemingly frivolous play. Heinze, according to Howe, uncovers a "range of socio-legal dualisms; master–servant, husband–wife, native–alien, parent–child, monarch–parliament, buyer–seller. The Comedy, argues, deploys concepts of 'comedy' and 'error' to reflect problematic socio-legal relationships that are based on traditional but changing models of socio-legal domination and subordination." Howe adds that, on Heinze's reading, "it is the viewpoint of the privileged male that is challenged in the play." In 190:
violence and discrimination without having to punish persons who hold provocative views.‘Central to the LSPD model’, according to Lesley Abdela, ‘it can be shown that western democratic states have taken moral and symbolic stands—not always perfectly or without contradiction— but certainly in more than peripheral, lip-service ways. Measures including non-discrimination laws, pluralist primary education (and bans on individually targeted stalking, harassment, or ‘fighting words’) convey the state’s moral and symbolic messages against intolerance or violence.’
268:, defines as "people whose sexual orientation derogates from a dominant heterosexual norm." Susan Sterett draws greater attention to Heinze's view of fluid and contingent sexual identities and orientations. Heinze, according to Sterett, "maps the discourse of sexual orientation onto postmodernist forms of knowledge, which emphasize the fragmentation of the legal subject." Conway Blake and Philip Dayle further explore Heinze's view "that sexual minorities have become pawns in what calls the international 'sensitivity game'. Blake and Dayle continue: 205:. Heinze argues that many traditions throughout history have recognised essential human goods, so if human rights are to play any distinct role, they must do something more than just restate human goods. Scrutinising the concept of a right, Heinze argues that it is only through free speech that human goods can become the objects of human rights, which entails the further conclusion that outside democracy the concept of human rights makes no sense – and simply collapses, at best, into a concept of human goods. 311:
of human goods. Many things are good, such as not being tortured, or having access to enough food, but these goods only manifest as objects of human rights when citizens are sufficiently able to agitate openly and candidly for them, including extensive opportunities to criticize their governments. Otherwise we are left, at best, with nothing but state-monopolized, managerial regimes of human goods, which, Heinze argues, are the arch-opposite of citizen-directed regimes of human rights.
275:
rooted in 'ancient' and 'indigenous' traditions. Heinze also notes the tendency of western states to eagerly demonstrate that they are not imposing a 'first world' agenda on 'traditional' societies. As a consequence, there has been a self-censoring forbearance in challenging southern states, as a kind of deference to indigenous cultural beliefs. In short, Heinze complains that many western states have been willing to tolerate human rights relativity in the context of sexuality.
99:' on the seemingly obvious assumption that 'justice' and 'injustice' are logical opposites. For Heinze, 'injustice', in ancient and modern Western languages, is a sheer etymological happenstance. 'Justice' and 'injustice' do appear as opposites within conventional, already pre-defined contexts, in which certain norms are uncritically assumed. Outside of such assumptions, however, the relationship between the two terms becomes far more complex. 20: 166:, Heinze identifies further problems of coherence within hate speech bans. Barendt writes that the bans, according to Heinze's critique, "are often justified as necessary to prevent discrimination against the targeted racial or other groups. But in fact they themselves discriminate between the groups protected by hate speech laws ( 286:
Heinze's criticisms of international law and institutions have also reached beyond the specific issues of free speech and sexuality. In other writing, he examines how inter-governmental and non-governmental organisations become politicised, therefore failing to adhere to their own professed mandates.
189:
Heinze acknowledges that hate speech has led to violence in Rwanda, the German Weimar Republic, the immediate post-Cold War Yugoslavia, and other weaker democracies. None of these, Heinze notes, were LSPDs. Full-fledged democracies, by contrast, have more legitimate and effective ways of combatting
310:
Heinze argues that the concept of human rights has become so diluted within international law and organizations as to carry little if any meaning. Heinze argues that governments and international organizations have failed to distinguish adequately between the concept of human rights and the concept
302:
Contrary to writers who advocate political compromise and piecemeal approaches, Heinze argues that the criterion of universally even-handed application of norms and standards necessarily inheres within any concept of human rights. He further warns that, insofar as human rights are designed to apply
259:
contends that, according to Heinze, the absence of any specific reference to sexual orientation or identity in earlier international human rights instruments "does not mean that fundamental rights are excluded from protection by these conventions." Simon Obendorf argues that "homosexual rights are
185:
Heinze reviews ongoing debates about the legality of dangerous, provocative or offensive speech. He concedes that some democracies may be unstable enough to require bans, but one that has crossed a discernible threshold to become what Heinze calls a ‘longstanding, stable and prosperous democracy’
274:
In this game, post-colonial regimes bolster their domestic authority by promoting nationalist campaigns based on ideas about sexuality, which depict minority sexual orientations as manifestations of Western decadence. Resistance to any programme of tolerance towards homosexuality is said to be
254:
human rights agenda, by the late 20th century, had resulted not merely in the exclusion of sexual orientation, but in a further mystification of it, which in turn was used to justify its continued exclusion. For Jennifer Wilson, Heinze's view in particular explains "the exclusion of transgender
212:‘Unthinkable’ Series, columnist Joe Humphreys summarises Heinze’s argument as follows: ‘If a sufficiently democratic environment does not exist, then the thing you are seeking as a “right” is merely a “good”, something desirable which a government may or may not provide.’ As of Spring 2022 264:", but questions "Eric Heinze's calls for a treaty-based instrument to codify and enforce principles of non-discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in international law." Obendorf challenges the concept of "sexual minorities" which Heinze, in his book 186:(LSPD) can only legitimately curtail expression within public discourse on ‘viewpoint-selective’ grounds under independently reviewable criteria of a ‘state of exception’ constituting a national security emergency. 102:
In order to overcome that recurring error, Heinze proposes a notion of 'post-classical' justice theory, using literary texts as examples. That project continues Heinze's earlier publications in
877:
Conway Blake and Philip Dayle, Beyond cross-cultural sensitivities: international human rights advocacy and sexuality in Jamaica, in Corinne Lennox & Matthew Waites (eds.) (2013)
861:
Conway Blake and Philip Dayle, Beyond cross-cultural sensitivities: international human rights advocacy and sexuality in Jamaica, in Corinne Lennox & Matthew Waites (eds.) (2013)
230:
adds: “it is no coincidence either that many authoritarian leaders throughout history have always first focused on that very right before they started to threaten the others too.”
95:, Heinze examines what he calls the 'classical' style of justice theory, running from Plato to Rawls. Classical justice theorists, Heinze argues, depart from notions of ' 36: 292: 197:, Heinze argues that internationally recognized human rights have collapsed in part because of institutional failures to distinguish between human 37: 492:
Adrian Howe, A 'Right to Passions'? Compassion's Sexed Asymmetry and a Minor Comedy of Errors, Law & Critique (2012), vol 23, pp 83-102.
623: 303:
universally to all states, irrespective of political system, they by definition never fully satisfy the requirements of a democratic state.
209: 386: 288: 510:
Adrian Howe, A 'Right to Passions'? Compassion's Sexed Asymmetry and a Minor Comedy of Errors, Law & Critique (2012), vol 23, p.99
501:
Adrian Howe, A 'Right to Passions'? Compassion's Sexed Asymmetry and a Minor Comedy of Errors, Law & Critique (2012), vol 23, p.98
1078: 607: 332: 60: 28: 1088: 378:); an Andres Public Interest grant (Harvard Law School); and a C. Clyde Ferguson Human Rights Fellowship (Harvard Law School). 648: 580: 217: 158:
has more effective and more legitimate ways of combating social intolerance, without having to restrict speech within the
389:
in Geneva and the United Nations Administrative Tribunal in New York. Heinze has advised the human rights organisations
103: 967: 138:, challenging their assumptions of a seemingly logical opposition between the concepts of 'justice' and 'injustice'. 243: 409: 336: 744:
Dag Øistein Endsjø, Lesbian, gay, bisexual and transgender rights and the religious relativism of human rights,
394: 299:
to ensure an entrenched and systemic "sidelining" of attention away from the gravest human rights situations.
256: 990:"Accueil : Français - Mission pour la Science et la Technologie de l'Ambassade de France aux Etats-Unis" 1083: 1073: 390: 672: 221: 382: 123: 367: 328: 119: 375: 371: 352: 344: 247: 80: 146:
In the area of human rights, Heinze has frequently challenged Western European restrictions on
603: 360: 348: 261: 147: 64: 109: 835:
Citing Eric Heinze, 'Discourses of Sexuality: Classical, Modernist and Post-Modernist', 67
1045: 239: 115: 320: 989: 415: 251: 175: 167: 731:
Jennifer Wilson, Horizontal Versus Vertical Compromise in Securing LGBT Civil Rights,
718:
Jennifer Wilson, Horizontal Versus Vertical Compromise in Securing LGBT Civil Rights,
220:(non-fiction published from February - July 2022). Reviewing the book for the Swedish 19: 1067: 356: 227: 159: 72: 374:); a Chateaubriand fellowship (French Ministry of Education); a Sheldon fellowship ( 340: 163: 76: 427:
Heinze is the author of several books on legal theory and philosophy, including:
170:) and those left unprotected (other cultural groups, the physically and mentally 35: 1027: 403: 296: 151: 130:, Heinze amplifies those themes. He reviews classical theories of justice, from 44: 941: 397:, and the Media Diversity Institute. He also serves on the Editorial Board of 324: 171: 135: 242:
and human rights. James M. Donovan summarises some of Heinze's criticisms of
155: 114:, the feminist scholar Adrian Howe examines how Heinze has innovated within 96: 975: 407:(journal of the Italian Society of Political Philosophy) (2021 – present), 255:
people from anti-discrimination laws." The Norwegian historian of religion
1058: 904:
Heinze, Eric (2008). "Even-handedness and the Politics of Human Rights".
892:
The United Nations Human Rights Council: A critique and early assessment
879:
Human Rights, Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity in The Commonwealth
863:
Human Rights, Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity in The Commonwealth
68: 1003: 848:
Susan Sterett, Husbands & Wives, Dangerousness & Dependence,
822:
Susan Sterett, Husbands & Wives, Dangerousness & Dependence,
287:
According to Rosa Freedman, Heinze explains how state members of the
865:(London: School of Advanced Study, University of London), pp 455-76. 532:
Eric Barendt, Religious Hatred Laws: Protecting Groups or Belief?,
131: 18: 881:(London: School of Advanced Study, University of London), p 465. 519:
Kay Goodall, Human Rights Pitted Against Man (II) - A Response,
246:. Donovan notes that, in Heinze's view, "the failure to include 624:"Why free speech should be the most highly valued human right" 796:
Simon Obendorf, Homosexual Rights and the Non-Western World,
783:
Simon Obendorf, Homosexual Rights and the Non-Western World,
770:
Simon Obendorf, Homosexual Rights and the Non-Western World,
757:
Simon Obendorf, Homosexual Rights and the Non-Western World,
673:"Yttrandefriheten - den mänskligaste rättigheten? | Dixikon" 927:. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 88–99, 129–137. 434:(Kluwer 1995) (Russian translation, Idea Press Moscow 2004) 873: 871: 438:
Of Innocence and Autonomy: Children, Sex and Human Rights
59:
is Professor of Law and Humanities at the School of Law
1059:
Queen Mary, University of London: Professional Web-page
370:; an Obermann Fellowship (Center for Advanced Studies, 649:"The Most Human Right: Why Free Speech Is Everything" 565:. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 111–116. 600:
The Most Human Right: Why Free Speech is Everything
474:
The Most Human Right: Why Free Speech is Everything
195:
The Most Human Right: Why Free Speech Is Everything
581:"Democracies, free Speech and the right to offend" 550:. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 69–78. 968:"Overview | Obermann Center for Advanced Studies" 705:James M Donovan, Baby Steps or One Fell Swoop?, 692:James M Donovan, Baby Steps or One Fell Swoop?, 936: 934: 366:Heinze's other awards include grants from the 8: 216:has been nominated for ‘The Next Big Idea’, 63:. He has made contributions in the areas of 1028:"The International Journal of Human Rights" 226:site the international human rights expert 399:The International Journal of Human Rights, 168:racial, ethnic, religious groups and gays 602:. Boston, Massachusetts: The MIT Press. 485: 440:(editor, Ashgate 2000 / Routledge 2017) 238:Heinze has also written on problems of 946:School of Law at Queen Mary University 925:Hate Speech and Democratic Citizenship 563:Hate Speech and Democratic Citizenship 548:Hate Speech and Democratic Citizenship 468:Hate Speech and Democratic Citizenship 404:Rivista Italiana di Filosofia Politica 401:and serves on the Advisory Boards for 282:Politics of International Human Rights 183:Hate Speech and Democratic Citizenship 162:. According to the free speech expert 521:International Journal of Human Rights 7: 574: 572: 410:Heliopolis: Culture CiviltĂ  Politica 154:" bans. Heinze argues that a modern 837:Nordic Journal of International Law 813:, Dordrecht: Nijhoff (1995), p 295. 387:International Commission of Jurists 289:United Nations Human Rights Council 894:(London: Routledge, 2013), p. 141. 733:Texas Journal of Women and the Law 720:Texas Journal of Women and the Law 456:The Logic of Constitutional Rights 291:, as well as its predecessor, the 14: 811:Sexual Orientation: A Human Right 446:(Routledge 2003 / Routledge 2017) 432:Sexual Orientation: A Human Right 266:Sexual Orientation: A Human Right 118:to offer alternative readings of 79:. He has also contributed to the 416:University of Bologna Law Review 385:, Heinze completed work for the 61:Queen Mary, University of London 33: 458:(Ashgate 2005 / Routledge 2017) 452:(Ashgate 2003 / Routledge 2017) 260:indeed worthy of protection at 108:. In an article in the journal 826:, vol 75 (1998), pp 1181-1213. 748:, vol 6:2, (2005), pp. 102-10. 579:Abdela, Lesley (22 May 2016). 470:(Oxford University Press 2016) 381:Before his appointment at the 1: 707:California Western Law Review 694:California Western Law Review 906:Harvard Human Rights Journal 850:Denver University Law Review 824:Denver University Law Review 150:, as embodied in so-called " 1034:. Vol. 20, no. 7. 1004:"Media Diversity Institute" 444:The Logic of Liberal Rights 244:international organisations 47:and democratic conversation 1105: 293:UN Human Rights Commission 1079:Harvard Law School alumni 798:Third World Legal Studies 785:Third World Legal Studies 772:Third World Legal Studies 759:Third World Legal Studies 696:, vol 38 (2001), pp 1-62. 536:(2011), vol 17, pp 41-53. 852:, vol 75 (1998), pp 1189 675:(in Swedish). 2022-06-17 523:, 14(7), 2010, 1165-1184 462:The Concept of Injustice 337:Freie Universität Berlin 128:The Concept of Injustice 122:. Citing the example of 93:The Concept of Injustice 1008:www.media-diversity.org 331:, Heinze enrolled as a 208:Writing in his regular 1089:Human rights activists 774:, 1998-99, pp 180-181. 761:, 1998-99, pp 179-204. 413:(2020 – present), and 53: 1044:See Douglas Grob, at 923:Heinze, Eric (2016). 709:, vol 38 (2001), p31. 598:Heinze, Eric (2022). 561:Heinze, Eric (2016). 546:Heinze, Eric (2016). 476:(The MIT Press, 2022) 450:The Logic of Equality 391:Amnesty International 353:University of Utrecht 22: 1032:Taylor & Francis 839:(1998), pp. 37 – 76. 722:, vol 18, pp 125-44. 383:University of London 361:University of Leiden 349:Fulbright fellowship 319:After receiving his 308:The Most Human Right 214:The Most Human Right 124:The Comedy of Errors 105:Law & Literature 746:Human Rights Review 368:Nuffield Foundation 347:, and, following a 329:UniversitĂŠ de Paris 120:William Shakespeare 972:obermann.uiowa.edu 800:, 1998-99, pp 199. 653:Next Big Idea Club 376:Harvard Law School 372:University of Iowa 345:Harvard Law School 257:Dag Øistein Endsjø 248:sexual orientation 111:Law & Critique 81:law and literature 54: 339:. He received a 262:international law 148:freedom of speech 38: 16:Legal philosopher 1096: 1047: 1042: 1036: 1035: 1024: 1018: 1017: 1015: 1014: 1000: 994: 993: 986: 980: 979: 974:. Archived from 964: 958: 957: 955: 953: 938: 929: 928: 920: 914: 913: 901: 895: 888: 882: 875: 866: 859: 853: 846: 840: 833: 827: 820: 814: 807: 801: 794: 788: 787:, 1998-99, p180. 781: 775: 768: 762: 755: 749: 742: 736: 735:, vol 18, p 137. 729: 723: 716: 710: 703: 697: 690: 684: 683: 681: 680: 669: 663: 662: 660: 659: 644: 638: 637: 635: 634: 620: 614: 613: 595: 589: 588: 576: 567: 566: 558: 552: 551: 543: 537: 530: 524: 517: 511: 508: 502: 499: 493: 490: 464:(Routledge 2013) 419:(2018–present). 357:Doctorate in Law 228:Hans Ingvar Roth 65:legal philosophy 40: 39: 1104: 1103: 1099: 1098: 1097: 1095: 1094: 1093: 1064: 1063: 1055: 1050: 1043: 1039: 1026: 1025: 1021: 1012: 1010: 1002: 1001: 997: 988: 987: 983: 966: 965: 961: 951: 949: 940: 939: 932: 922: 921: 917: 903: 902: 898: 890:Rosa Freedman, 889: 885: 876: 869: 860: 856: 847: 843: 834: 830: 821: 817: 808: 804: 795: 791: 782: 778: 769: 765: 756: 752: 743: 739: 730: 726: 717: 713: 704: 700: 691: 687: 678: 676: 671: 670: 666: 657: 655: 646: 645: 641: 632: 630: 628:The Irish Times 622: 621: 617: 610: 597: 596: 592: 578: 577: 570: 560: 559: 555: 545: 544: 540: 531: 527: 518: 514: 509: 505: 500: 496: 491: 487: 483: 425: 335:scholar at the 317: 284: 236: 144: 116:critical theory 89: 52: 51: 50: 49: 48: 41: 34: 31: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1102: 1100: 1092: 1091: 1086: 1081: 1076: 1066: 1065: 1062: 1061: 1054: 1053:External links 1051: 1049: 1048: 1037: 1019: 995: 981: 978:on 2012-05-30. 959: 930: 915: 896: 883: 867: 854: 841: 828: 815: 802: 789: 776: 763: 750: 737: 724: 711: 698: 685: 664: 647:Heinze, Eric. 639: 615: 609:978-0262046459 608: 590: 568: 553: 538: 525: 512: 503: 494: 484: 482: 479: 478: 477: 471: 465: 459: 453: 447: 441: 435: 424: 421: 355:, completed a 316: 313: 283: 280: 279: 278: 277: 276: 252:United Nations 235: 232: 143: 140: 88: 85: 69:justice theory 42: 32: 29:Heinze's voice 27: 26: 25: 24: 23: 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1101: 1090: 1087: 1085: 1084:Legal writers 1082: 1080: 1077: 1075: 1074:Living people 1072: 1071: 1069: 1060: 1057: 1056: 1052: 1046: 1041: 1038: 1033: 1029: 1023: 1020: 1009: 1005: 999: 996: 991: 985: 982: 977: 973: 969: 963: 960: 947: 943: 942:"Eric Heinze" 937: 935: 931: 926: 919: 916: 911: 907: 900: 897: 893: 887: 884: 880: 874: 872: 868: 864: 858: 855: 851: 845: 842: 838: 832: 829: 825: 819: 816: 812: 809:Eric Heinze, 806: 803: 799: 793: 790: 786: 780: 777: 773: 767: 764: 760: 754: 751: 747: 741: 738: 734: 728: 725: 721: 715: 712: 708: 702: 699: 695: 689: 686: 674: 668: 665: 654: 650: 643: 640: 629: 625: 619: 616: 611: 605: 601: 594: 591: 586: 585:OpenDemocracy 582: 575: 573: 569: 564: 557: 554: 549: 542: 539: 535: 529: 526: 522: 516: 513: 507: 504: 498: 495: 489: 486: 480: 475: 472: 469: 466: 463: 460: 457: 454: 451: 448: 445: 442: 439: 436: 433: 430: 429: 428: 422: 420: 418: 417: 412: 411: 406: 405: 400: 396: 392: 388: 384: 379: 377: 373: 369: 364: 362: 358: 354: 350: 346: 342: 338: 334: 330: 326: 322: 314: 312: 309: 304: 300: 298: 294: 290: 281: 273: 272: 271: 270: 269: 267: 263: 258: 253: 249: 245: 241: 233: 231: 229: 225: 224: 219: 215: 211: 206: 204: 200: 196: 191: 187: 184: 179: 177: 173: 169: 165: 161: 160:public sphere 157: 153: 149: 141: 139: 137: 133: 129: 125: 121: 117: 113: 112: 107: 106: 100: 98: 94: 86: 84: 82: 78: 74: 73:jurisprudence 70: 66: 62: 58: 46: 30: 21: 1040: 1031: 1022: 1011:. Retrieved 1007: 998: 984: 976:the original 971: 962: 950:. Retrieved 945: 924: 918: 909: 905: 899: 891: 886: 878: 862: 857: 849: 844: 836: 831: 823: 818: 810: 805: 797: 792: 784: 779: 771: 766: 758: 753: 745: 740: 732: 727: 719: 714: 706: 701: 693: 688: 677:. Retrieved 667: 656:. Retrieved 652: 642: 631:. Retrieved 627: 618: 599: 593: 584: 562: 556: 547: 541: 533: 528: 520: 515: 506: 497: 488: 473: 467: 461: 455: 449: 443: 437: 431: 426: 423:Publications 414: 408: 402: 398: 380: 365: 341:Juris Doctor 318: 307: 305: 301: 295:, have used 285: 265: 237: 222: 213: 207: 202: 198: 194: 192: 188: 182: 181:In his book 180: 176:transsexuals 164:Eric Barendt 145: 127: 110: 104: 101: 92: 90: 87:Legal Theory 77:human rights 56: 55: 534:Res Publica 297:bloc voting 250:within the 210:Irish Times 152:hate speech 142:Free speech 57:Eric Heinze 45:free speech 1068:Categories 1013:2016-02-18 679:2022-08-02 658:2022-08-02 633:2022-08-02 481:References 201:and human 83:movement. 327:from the 240:sexuality 234:Sexuality 218:Season 18 156:democracy 97:injustice 952:13 March 325:MaĂŽtrise 172:disabled 912:: 7–46. 395:Liberty 359:at the 351:at the 321:Licence 223:Dixicon 948:. QMUL 606:  315:Career 199:rights 75:, and 343:from 203:goods 136:Rawls 132:Plato 954:2015 604:ISBN 333:DAAD 323:and 178:)." 306:In 193:In 134:to 91:In 43:On 1070:: 1030:. 1006:. 970:. 944:. 933:^ 910:21 908:. 870:^ 651:. 626:. 583:. 571:^ 393:, 363:. 174:, 71:, 67:, 1016:. 992:. 956:. 682:. 661:. 636:. 612:. 587:.

Index


Heinze's voice
free speech
Queen Mary, University of London
legal philosophy
justice theory
jurisprudence
human rights
law and literature
injustice
Law & Literature
Law & Critique
critical theory
William Shakespeare
The Comedy of Errors
Plato
Rawls
freedom of speech
hate speech
democracy
public sphere
Eric Barendt
racial, ethnic, religious groups and gays
disabled
transsexuals
Irish Times
Season 18
Dixicon
Hans Ingvar Roth
sexuality

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑