Knowledge (XXG)

Hume's fork

Source đź“ť

27: 523:) held that logical statements such as these contained the most formal reality, since they are always true and unchanging, Hume held that, while true, they contain no formal reality, because the truth of the statements rests on the definitions of the words involved, and not on actual things in the world, since there is no such thing as a true triangle or exact equality of length in the world. So for this reason, relations of ideas cannot be used to prove matters of fact. 527:
cannot be used to prove matters of fact. Because of this, matters of fact have no certainty and therefore cannot be used to prove anything. Only certain things can be used to prove other things for certain, but only things about the world can be used to prove other things about the world. But since we can't cross the fork, nothing is both certain and about the world, only one or the other, and so it is impossible to prove something about the world with certainty.
534:(for example) as a matter of fact. If God is not literally made up of physical matter, and does not have an observable effect on the world , making a statement about God is not a matter of fact. Therefore, a statement about God must be a relation of ideas. In this case if we prove the statement "God exists," it doesn't really tell us anything about the world; it is just playing with words. It is easy to see how Hume's fork voids the causal argument and the 511:
dropped on Earth it went down, this does not make it logically necessary that in the future rocks will fall when in the same circumstances. Things of this nature rely upon the future conforming to the same principles which governed the past. But that isn't something that we can know based on past experience—all past experience could tell us is that in the past, the future has resembled the past.
510:
Second, Hume claims that our belief in cause-and-effect relationships between events is not grounded on reason, but rather arises merely by habit or custom. Suppose one states: "Whenever someone on earth lets go of a stone it falls." While we can grant that in every instance thus far when a rock was
514:
Third, Hume notes that relations of ideas can be used only to prove other relations of ideas, and mean nothing outside of the context of how they relate to each other, and therefore tell us nothing about the world. Take the statement "An equilateral triangle has three sides of equal length." While
526:
The results claimed by Hume as consequences of his fork are drastic. According to him, relations of ideas can be proved with certainty (by using other relations of ideas), however, they don't really mean anything about the world. Since they don't mean anything about the world, relations of ideas
538:
for the existence of a non-observable God. However, this does not mean that the validity of Hume's fork would imply that God definitely does not exist, only that it would imply that the existence of God cannot be proven as a matter of fact without worldly evidence.
351:
Hume's fork remains basic in Anglo-American philosophy. Many deceptions and confusions are foisted by surreptitious or unwitting conversion of a synthetic claim to an analytic claim, rendered true by necessity but merely a tautology, for instance the
554:, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but 402:
discoverable by the mere operation of thought ... Matters of fact, which are the second object of human reason, are not ascertained in the same manner; nor is our evidence of their truth, however great, of a like nature with the foregoing.
503:
does not exist in science. First, Hume notes that statements of the second type can never be entirely certain, due to the fallibility of our senses, the possibility of deception (see e.g. the modern
286:—combining meanings of terms with states of facts, yet known true without experience of the particular instance—replacing the two prongs of Hume's fork with a three-pronged-fork thesis ( 316:
entailing both necessity and aprioricity via logic on one side and, on the other side, demand empirical verification, altogether restricting philosophical discourse to claims
1126: 332:, as every term in any statement has its meaning contingent on a vast network of knowledge and belief, the speaker's conception of the entire world. By the early 1970s, 312:
and asserted Hume's fork, so called, while hinging it at language—the analytic/synthetic division—while presuming that by holding to analyticity, they could develop a
979: 972: 560: 410: 291: 214: 792: 986: 771: 1120: 1000: 941: 708: 197:—that no amount of examination of cases will logically entail the conformity of unexamined cases—and supported Hume's aim to position 507:
theory) and other arguments made by philosophical skeptics. It is always possible that any given statement about the world is false.
1147: 359:. Simply put, Hume's fork has limitations. Related concerns are Hume's distinction of demonstrative versus probable reasoning and 1157: 1096: 1152: 677: 628: 426: 226: 101: 746: 348:
are the same star, they are the same star by necessity, but this is known true by a human only through relevant experience.
614: 1014: 1007: 297: 301: 899: 595: 965: 767: 1074: 438: 79: 73: 934: 446: 117: 649: 619: 473: 325: 270: 265: 206: 1086: 703: 329: 234: 20: 1033: 464: 1064: 1043: 205:
while combatting allegedly rampant "sophistry and illusion" by philosophers and religionists. Being a
1038: 787: 645: 535: 460: 253: 194: 1162: 1059: 927: 42: 1167: 993: 451: 305: 275: 218: 129: 68: 49:'s emphatic, 1730s division between "relations of ideas" and "matters of fact." (Alternatively, 725: 542:
Hume rejected the idea of any meaningful statement that did not fall into this schema, saying:
721: 202: 143: 531: 379:
All the objects of human reason or enquiry may naturally be divided into two kinds, to wit,
353: 155: 150:, whereas a synthetic statement, concerning external states of affairs, may be false, like 729: 317: 421:
Hume's fork is often stated in such a way that statements are divided up into two types:
189:, whereas assertions of "real existence" and traits, being synthetic, are contingent and 668: 610: 504: 313: 222: 159: 26: 282:
into the experience of space and time. Kant thus reasoned existence of the synthetic
1141: 468: 360: 261: 64: 55: 1113: 257: 137: 121: 38: 240:. Still, Hume's fork is a useful starting point to anchor philosophical scrutiny. 488:, and ideas of mathematics and logic. Into the second class fall statements like 1091: 1080: 699: 587: 551: 430: 333: 321: 230: 210: 182: 163: 113: 109: 221:." In the 1930s, the logical empiricists staked Hume's fork. Yet in the 1950s, 950: 396: 364: 279: 249: 46: 624: 555: 520: 500: 434: 96: 71:, Hume's fork asserts that all statements are exclusively either "analytic 67:
1780s characterization of Hume's thesis, and furthered in the 1930s by the
905: 547: 388: 198: 672: 392: 375:
The first distinction is between two different areas of human study:
142:. An analytic statement is true via its terms' meanings alone, hence 60: 516: 345: 341: 278:
by the mind's aligning the environmental input by arranging those
178: 25: 363:. Hume makes other, important two-category distinctions, such as 530:
If accepted, Hume's fork makes it pointless to try to prove the
923: 459:
In modern terminology, members of the first group are known as
87:
or, however apparently probable, are unknowable without exact
919: 726:"The problem of metaphysics: The 'new' metaphysics; Modality" 174:
is knowable only upon, experience in the area of interest.
328:
undermined the analytic/synthetic division by explicating
177:
By Hume's fork, sheer conceptual derivations (ostensibly,
162:, whereas the contingent hinges on the world's state, a 615:
ch. 2 "Hume's theory of knowledge (I): 'Hume's fork' "
274:, where Kant attributed to the mind a causal role in 83:," which, respectively, are universally true by mere 620:
Hume's Epistemology and Metaphysics: An Introduction
30:
Hume's fork contrasted with Kant's trident/pitchfork
1127:
Extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence
1105: 1052: 1026: 957: 833:
Bacon to Kant: An Introduction to Modern Philosophy
745:Leah Henderson, "The problem of induction", sec. 2 594:, rev 2nd edn (New York: St Martin's Press, 1984), 818:Nicholas Bunnin & Jiyuan Yu. "Hume's Fork". 445:Statements about the world. These are synthetic, 193:. Hume's own, simpler, distinction concerned the 640:Nicholas Bunnin & Jiyuan Yu, "Hume's fork", 807:Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy 980:An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals 844:Nicholas Bunnin and Jiyuan Yu, "Hume's Fork". 642:The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy 631:introducing Kant's formulation of Hume's fork. 1034:Argument for the existence of God from design 935: 480:Into the first class fall statements such as 8: 846:Blackwell's Dictionary of Western Philosophy 820:Blackwell's Dictionary of Western Philosophy 724:& Meghan Sullivan, "Metaphysics", § 3.1 942: 928: 920: 973:An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 901:An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 561:An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 411:An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 515:some earlier philosophers (most notably 387:. Of the first kind are the sciences of 209:, Kant asserted both the hope of a true 793:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 573: 217:by defying Hume's fork to declare the " 987:Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary 870:Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 858:Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 583: 581: 579: 577: 546:If we take in our hand any volume; of 371:Relations of ideas and matters of fact 252:, as in Hume's fork as well as Hume's 53:may refer to what is otherwise termed 1121:A Treatise of Human Nature (Abstract) 1001:Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion 300:, Newton's theory fell to Einstein's 292:Newton's law of universal gravitation 215:Newton's law of universal gravitation 185:), being analytic, are necessary and 7: 881: 782: 780: 704:"The analytic/synthetic distinction" 695: 693: 691: 664: 662: 660: 658: 606: 604: 19:For the novel of the same name, see 904:. London: A. Millar. Archived from 751:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 734:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 709:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 425:Statements about ideas. These are 14: 367:and as impressions versus ideas. 170:is knowable without, whereas the 120:, and the statement's purported 884:, p. 166, emphasis removed 809:. Clarendon Press, 2004. p. 28. 678:History of Philosophy Quarterly 158:, the necessary is true in all 490:"the sun rises in the morning" 467:. This terminology comes from 227:analytic/synthetic distinction 94:By Hume's fork, a statement's 41:, is a tenet elaborating upon 1: 764:The Suasive Art of David Hume 486:"all bachelors are unmarried" 463:and members of the latter as 1015:The History of Great Britain 302:general theory of relativity 1097:Price–specie flow mechanism 790:, in Edward N. Zalta, ed., 749:, in Edward N. Zalta, ed., 706:, in Edward N. Zalta, ed., 256:, was taken as a threat to 1184: 966:A Treatise of Human Nature 768:Princeton University Press 592:A Dictionary of Philosophy 336:established the necessary 308:rejected Kant's synthetic 18: 1075:The Missing Shade of Blue 499:Hume wants to prove that 482:"all bodies are extended" 304:. In the late 1920s, the 1148:Concepts in epistemology 623:(London & New York: 213:, and a literal view of 102:analytic or is synthetic 1158:Conceptual distinctions 673:"Hume's fork revisited" 474:Critique of Pure Reason 326:Willard Van Orman Quine 324:. In the early 1950s, 271:Critique of Pure Reason 266:Transcendental Idealism 207:transcendental idealist 148:Bachelors are unmarried 1153:Philosophy of language 1087:Scottish Enlightenment 1008:The History of England 835:, 2nd Edition, p. 218. 565: 494:"all bodies have mass" 465:synthetic propositions 365:beliefs versus desires 330:ontological relativity 260:'s theory of motion. 31: 898:Hume, David (1777) . 872:, Section IV, Part I. 544: 461:analytic propositions 29: 1039:Problem of induction 646:Blackwell Publishing 536:ontological argument 254:problem of induction 229:. And in the 1970s, 195:problem of induction 108:—its agreement with 822:. Blackwell, 2004. 747:"Hume on induction" 306:logical positivists 264:responded with his 152:Bachelors age badly 69:logical empiricists 21:Hume's Fork (novel) 994:Four Dissertations 848:. Blackwell, 2004. 381:relations of ideas 290:) and thus saving 276:sensory experience 219:synthetic a priori 154:. By mere logical 144:true by definition 104:, the statement's 43:British empiricist 32: 16:English philosophy 1135: 1134: 831:Garrett Thomson, 722:Peter van Inwagen 471:(Introduction to 203:empirical science 63:.) As phrased in 1175: 1060:Hume's principle 1044:Is–ought problem 944: 937: 930: 921: 916: 914: 913: 885: 879: 873: 867: 861: 855: 849: 842: 836: 829: 823: 816: 810: 803: 797: 784: 775: 766:(Princeton, NJ: 760: 754: 743: 737: 719: 713: 697: 686: 666: 653: 638: 632: 608: 599: 585: 558:and illusion. — 532:existence of God 355:No true Scotsman 288:Kant's pitchfork 233:established the 141: 133: 77:" or "synthetic 1183: 1182: 1178: 1177: 1176: 1174: 1173: 1172: 1138: 1137: 1136: 1131: 1101: 1048: 1022: 953: 948: 911: 909: 897: 894: 889: 888: 880: 876: 868: 864: 856: 852: 843: 839: 830: 826: 817: 813: 805:Hanna, Robert, 804: 800: 785: 778: 761: 757: 744: 740: 730:Edward N. Zalta 720: 716: 698: 689: 667: 656: 639: 635: 609: 602: 586: 575: 570: 477:, Section IV). 449:, and knowable 385:matters of fact 373: 340:, since if the 246: 225:undermined its 166:basis. And the 160:possible worlds 135: 127: 65:Immanuel Kant's 24: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1181: 1179: 1171: 1170: 1165: 1160: 1155: 1150: 1140: 1139: 1133: 1132: 1130: 1129: 1124: 1117: 1109: 1107: 1103: 1102: 1100: 1099: 1094: 1089: 1084: 1077: 1072: 1067: 1062: 1056: 1054: 1050: 1049: 1047: 1046: 1041: 1036: 1030: 1028: 1024: 1023: 1021: 1020: 1019: 1018: 1004: 997: 990: 983: 976: 969: 961: 959: 955: 954: 949: 947: 946: 939: 932: 924: 918: 917: 893: 890: 887: 886: 874: 862: 850: 837: 824: 811: 798: 796:(Spring 2013). 786:James Fetzer, 776: 755: 753:(Spring 2020). 738: 736:(Spring 2020). 714: 687: 669:Georges Dicker 654: 633: 611:Georges Dicker 600: 572: 571: 569: 566: 505:brain in a vat 457: 456: 443: 419: 418: 417: 416: 415: 414: 372: 369: 314:logical syntax 248:Hume's strong 245: 242: 110:the real world 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1180: 1169: 1166: 1164: 1161: 1159: 1156: 1154: 1151: 1149: 1146: 1145: 1143: 1128: 1125: 1123: 1122: 1118: 1116: 1115: 1111: 1110: 1108: 1104: 1098: 1095: 1093: 1090: 1088: 1085: 1082: 1078: 1076: 1073: 1071: 1068: 1066: 1063: 1061: 1058: 1057: 1055: 1051: 1045: 1042: 1040: 1037: 1035: 1032: 1031: 1029: 1025: 1017: 1016: 1012: 1011: 1010: 1009: 1005: 1003: 1002: 998: 996: 995: 991: 989: 988: 984: 982: 981: 977: 975: 974: 970: 968: 967: 963: 962: 960: 956: 952: 945: 940: 938: 933: 931: 926: 925: 922: 908:on 2018-07-10 907: 903: 902: 896: 895: 891: 883: 878: 875: 871: 866: 863: 860:, Section II. 859: 854: 851: 847: 841: 838: 834: 828: 825: 821: 815: 812: 808: 802: 799: 795: 794: 789: 788:"Carl Hempel" 783: 781: 777: 773: 769: 765: 759: 756: 752: 748: 742: 739: 735: 731: 727: 723: 718: 715: 711: 710: 705: 701: 696: 694: 692: 688: 684: 680: 679: 674: 670: 665: 663: 661: 659: 655: 651: 647: 644:(Malden, MA: 643: 637: 634: 630: 626: 622: 621: 616: 612: 607: 605: 601: 597: 593: 589: 584: 582: 580: 578: 574: 567: 564: 563: 562: 557: 553: 549: 543: 540: 537: 533: 528: 524: 522: 518: 512: 508: 506: 502: 497: 495: 491: 487: 483: 478: 476: 475: 470: 466: 462: 454: 453: 448: 444: 441: 440: 436: 432: 428: 424: 423: 422: 413: 412: 407: 406: 405: 404: 401: 398: 394: 390: 386: 382: 378: 377: 376: 370: 368: 366: 362: 358: 356: 349: 347: 343: 339: 335: 331: 327: 323: 322:false or true 319: 315: 311: 307: 303: 299: 295: 293: 289: 285: 281: 277: 273: 272: 267: 263: 262:Immanuel Kant 259: 255: 251: 243: 241: 239: 238: 232: 228: 224: 223:W. V. O Quine 220: 216: 212: 208: 204: 200: 196: 192: 188: 184: 180: 175: 173: 169: 165: 161: 157: 153: 149: 145: 140: 139: 132: 131: 125: 124: 119: 115: 111: 107: 103: 99: 98: 92: 90: 86: 82: 81: 76: 75: 70: 66: 62: 59:, a tenet of 58: 57: 52: 48: 44: 40: 36: 28: 22: 1119: 1114:Hume Studies 1112: 1069: 1013: 1006: 999: 992: 985: 978: 971: 964: 910:. Retrieved 906:the original 900: 877: 869: 865: 857: 853: 845: 840: 832: 827: 819: 814: 806: 801: 791: 763: 758: 750: 741: 733: 717: 712:(Fall 2018). 707: 685:(4):327–342. 682: 676: 641: 636: 618: 591: 559: 545: 541: 529: 525: 513: 509: 498: 493: 489: 485: 481: 479: 472: 458: 452:a posteriori 450: 437: 420: 409: 400: 384: 380: 374: 354: 350: 346:Evening Star 342:Morning Star 338:a posteriori 337: 309: 296: 287: 283: 269: 268:in his 1781 247: 237:a posteriori 236: 201:on par with 191:a posteriori 190: 186: 176: 172:a posteriori 171: 167: 164:metaphysical 151: 147: 138:a posteriori 136: 128: 122: 105: 95: 93: 88: 84: 80:a posteriori 78: 72: 54: 50: 45:philosopher 39:epistemology 34: 33: 1081:Of Miracles 1070:Hume's fork 762:M. A. Box, 700:Georges Rey 681:, 1991 Oct; 588:Antony Flew 552:metaphysics 334:Saul Kripke 231:Saul Kripke 211:metaphysics 183:mathematics 112:—either is 51:Hume's fork 35:Hume's fork 1163:David Hume 1142:Categories 1092:Empiricism 1065:Hume's law 1053:Philosophy 951:David Hume 912:2015-08-31 892:References 550:or school 447:contingent 397:Arithmetic 361:Hume's law 320:as either 318:verifiable 280:sense data 250:empiricism 235:necessary 126:either is 118:contingent 100:either is 89:experience 85:definition 56:Hume's law 47:David Hume 1168:Humeanism 1027:Criticism 882:Hume 1777 772:pp. 39–41 770:, 1990), 648:, 2004), 627:, 1998), 625:Routledge 556:sophistry 521:Descartes 501:certainty 431:necessary 123:knowledge 114:necessary 548:divinity 439:a priori 435:knowable 427:analytic 389:Geometry 344:and the 310:a priori 284:a priori 199:humanism 187:a priori 168:a priori 156:validity 130:a priori 74:a priori 1106:Related 732:, ed., 393:Algebra 298:In 1919 244:History 146:, like 97:meaning 596:p. 156 492:, and 433:, and 395:, and 383:, and 258:Newton 134:or is 116:or is 61:ethics 958:Books 728:, in 650:p 314 629:p. 41 568:Notes 517:Plato 179:logic 106:truth 37:, in 519:and 469:Kant 357:move 181:and 399:... 1144:: 779:^ 702:, 690:^ 675:, 671:, 657:^ 617:, 613:, 603:^ 590:, 576:^ 496:. 484:, 429:, 408:— 391:, 294:. 91:. 1083:" 1079:" 943:e 936:t 929:v 915:. 774:. 683:8 652:. 598:. 455:. 442:. 23:.

Index

Hume's Fork (novel)
Four lines of text. The top two show Hume's fork, with analytic, a priori, and necessary in a line, followed by synthetic, a posteriori, and contingent. Below, Kant's trident, where synthetic statements may also be a priori.
epistemology
British empiricist
David Hume
Hume's law
ethics
Immanuel Kant's
logical empiricists
a priori
a posteriori
meaning
analytic or is synthetic
the real world
necessary
contingent
knowledge
a priori
a posteriori
true by definition
validity
possible worlds
metaphysical
logic
mathematics
problem of induction
humanism
empirical science
transcendental idealist
metaphysics

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑