Knowledge (XXG)

Hilbert's program

Source đź“ť

33: 284:
in this case it is not possible to give finitary proofs of reasonably strong theories. On the other hand, Gödel himself suggested the possibility of giving finitary consistency proofs using finitary methods that cannot be formalized in Peano arithmetic, so he seems to have had a more liberal view of what finitary methods might be allowed. A few years later,
146:
set of axioms which is capable of expressing arithmetic can never be complete: it is possible to construct a statement that can be shown to be true, but that cannot be derived from the formal rules of the system. In his second theorem, he showed that such a system could not prove its own consistency,
283:
The question of whether there are finitary consistency proofs of strong theories is difficult to answer, mainly because there is no generally accepted definition of a "finitary proof". Most mathematicians in proof theory seem to regard finitary mathematics as being contained in Peano arithmetic, and
200:
showed that most of the goals of Hilbert's program were impossible to achieve, at least if interpreted in the most obvious way. Gödel's second incompleteness theorem shows that any consistent theory powerful enough to encode addition and multiplication of integers cannot prove its own consistency.
267:
Although it is not possible to prove completeness for systems that can express at least the Peano arithmetic (or, more generally, that have a computable set of axioms), it is possible to prove forms of completeness for many other interesting systems. An example of a non-trivial theory for which
147:
so it certainly cannot be used to prove the consistency of anything stronger with certainty. This refuted Hilbert's assumption that a finitistic system could be used to prove the consistency of itself, and therefore could not prove everything else.
248:, can be viewed as natural continuations of Hilbert's original program. Much of it can be salvaged by changing its goals slightly (Zach 2005), and with the following modifications some of it was successfully completed: 314:
and others, and one can again debate about exactly how finitary or constructive these proofs are. (The theories that have been proved consistent by these methods are quite strong, and include most "ordinary"
220:
A theory such as Peano arithmetic cannot even prove its own consistency, so a restricted "finitistic" subset of it certainly cannot prove the consistency of more powerful theories such as set theory.
169:
Consistency: a proof that no contradiction can be obtained in the formalism of mathematics. This consistency proof should preferably use only "finitistic" reasoning about finite mathematical objects.
318:
Although there is no algorithm for deciding the truth of statements in Peano arithmetic, there are many interesting and non-trivial theories for which such algorithms have been found. For example,
209:
mathematical true statements within a formal system, as any attempt at such a formalism will omit some true mathematical statements. There is no complete, consistent extension of even
306:. If this transfinite induction is accepted as a finitary method, then one can assert that there is a finitary proof of the consistency of Peano arithmetic. More powerful subsets of 223:
There is no algorithm to decide the truth (or provability) of statements in any consistent extension of Peano arithmetic. Strictly speaking, this negative solution to the
142:, published in 1931, showed that Hilbert's program was unattainable for key areas of mathematics. In his first theorem, Gödel showed that any consistent system with a 192: 139: 54: 468: 353: 116:
were found to suffer from paradoxes and inconsistencies. As a solution, Hilbert proposed to ground all existing theories to a finite,
109: 76: 257: 155:
The main goal of Hilbert's program was to provide secure foundations for all mathematics. In particular, this should include:
496: 289: 413:
104:485–94. Translated by W. Ewald as 'The Grounding of Elementary Number Theory', pp. 266–273 in Mancosu (ed., 1998)
132:, could be proven in terms of simpler systems. Ultimately, the consistency of all of mathematics could be reduced to basic 420: 227:
appeared a few years after Gödel's theorem, because at the time the notion of an algorithm had not been precisely defined.
486: 47: 41: 273: 172:
Conservation: a proof that any result about "real objects" obtained using reasoning about "ideal objects" (such as
113: 331: 429: 348: 58: 277: 307: 159:
A formulation of all mathematics; in other words all mathematical statements should be written in a precise
256:
mathematics, it is possible to formalize essentially all the mathematics that anyone uses. In particular
491: 398: 293: 214: 374: 224: 179: 117: 245: 335: 237: 424: 182:: there should be an algorithm for deciding the truth or falsity of any mathematical statement. 327: 323: 292:
for Peano arithmetic. The only part of this proof that was not clearly finitary was a certain
261: 264:, gives a satisfactory and generally accepted formalism for almost all current mathematics. 166:
Completeness: a proof that all true mathematical statements can be proved in the formalism.
463: 285: 269: 160: 334:, this algorithm can be regarded as an algorithm to decide the truth of any statement in 338:. This is substantial as few people would consider Euclidean geometry a trivial theory. 300: 297: 459: 17: 480: 319: 311: 197: 129: 105: 436: 241: 210: 415:
From Brouwer to Hilbert: The debate on the foundations of mathematics in the 1920s
173: 93: 143: 133: 125: 128:. Hilbert proposed that the consistency of more complicated systems, such as 396:
G. Gentzen, 1936/1969. Die Widerspruchfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie.
89:
Attempt to formalize all of mathematics, based on a finite set of axioms
101: 444: 381:(Spring 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 121: 322:
found an algorithm that can decide the truth of any statement in
402:
112:493–565. Translated as 'The consistency of arithmetic', in
373:
Zach, Richard (2023), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.),
26: 409:
D. Hilbert. 'Die Grundlegung der elementaren Zahlenlehre'.
108:in the early 1920s, was a proposed solution to the 163:, and manipulated according to well defined rules. 201:This presents a challenge to Hilbert's program: 176:sets) can be proved without using ideal objects. 425:Partial realizations of Hilbert's program (pdf) 326:(more precisely, he proved that the theory of 124:, and provide a proof that these axioms were 8: 252:Although it is not possible to formalize 77:Learn how and when to remove this message 439:, 2006. Hilbert's Program Then and Now. 40:This article includes a list of general 404:The collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen 379:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 365: 186: 310:have been given consistency proofs by 112:, when early attempts to clarify the 7: 417:, Oxford University Press. New York. 469:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 231: 354:Foundational crisis of mathematics 236:Many current lines of research in 110:foundational crisis of mathematics 46:it lacks sufficient corresponding 25: 272:has been proved is the theory of 205:It is not possible to formalize 31: 193:Gödel's incompleteness theorems 187:Gödel's incompleteness theorems 140:Gödel's incompleteness theorems 151:Statement of Hilbert's program 1: 232:Hilbert's program after Gödel 274:algebraically closed fields 258:Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory 513: 406:, M. E. Szabo (ed.), 1969. 190: 114:foundations of mathematics 430:Journal of Symbolic Logic 349:Grundlagen der Mathematik 330:is decidable). Given the 308:second-order arithmetic 150: 61:more precise citations. 18:Hilbert's Program 411:Mathematische Annalen 399:Mathematische Annalen 332:Cantor–Dedekind axiom 294:transfinite induction 215:computably enumerable 225:Entscheidungsproblem 460:"Hilbert's Program" 441:Philosophy of Logic 375:"Hilbert's Program" 246:reverse mathematics 497:Hilbert's problems 487:Mathematical logic 445:arXiv:math/0508572 336:Euclidean geometry 328:real closed fields 238:mathematical logic 324:analytic geometry 290:consistency proof 262:first-order logic 98:Hilbert's program 87: 86: 79: 16:(Redirected from 504: 473: 464:Zalta, Edward N. 389: 388: 387: 386: 370: 260:, combined with 211:Peano arithmetic 100:, formulated by 82: 75: 71: 68: 62: 57:this article by 48:inline citations 35: 34: 27: 21: 512: 511: 507: 506: 505: 503: 502: 501: 477: 476: 457: 454: 393: 392: 384: 382: 372: 371: 367: 362: 345: 304: 234: 195: 189: 161:formal language 153: 90: 83: 72: 66: 63: 53:Please help to 52: 36: 32: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 510: 508: 500: 499: 494: 489: 479: 478: 475: 474: 458:Richard Zach. 453: 452:External links 450: 449: 448: 434: 418: 407: 391: 390: 364: 363: 361: 358: 357: 356: 351: 344: 341: 340: 339: 316: 302: 281: 278:characteristic 265: 233: 230: 229: 228: 221: 218: 217:set of axioms. 191:Main article: 188: 185: 184: 183: 177: 170: 167: 164: 152: 149: 104:mathematician 88: 85: 84: 39: 37: 30: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 509: 498: 495: 493: 490: 488: 485: 484: 482: 471: 470: 465: 461: 456: 455: 451: 446: 442: 438: 435: 432: 431: 426: 422: 419: 416: 412: 408: 405: 401: 400: 395: 394: 380: 376: 369: 366: 359: 355: 352: 350: 347: 346: 342: 337: 333: 329: 325: 321: 317: 315:mathematics.) 313: 312:Gaisi Takeuti 309: 305: 299: 295: 291: 287: 282: 279: 275: 271: 266: 263: 259: 255: 251: 250: 249: 247: 243: 239: 226: 222: 219: 216: 212: 208: 204: 203: 202: 199: 194: 181: 178: 175: 171: 168: 165: 162: 158: 157: 156: 148: 145: 141: 137: 135: 131: 130:real analysis 127: 123: 119: 115: 111: 107: 106:David Hilbert 103: 99: 95: 81: 78: 70: 60: 56: 50: 49: 43: 38: 29: 28: 19: 492:Proof theory 467: 440: 428: 421:S.G. Simpson 414: 410: 403: 397: 383:, retrieved 378: 368: 270:completeness 253: 242:proof theory 235: 206: 196: 180:Decidability 154: 138: 97: 91: 73: 64: 45: 443:5:411–447, 433:53:349–363. 213:based on a 174:uncountable 94:mathematics 59:introducing 481:Categories 385:2023-07-05 360:References 296:up to the 240:, such as 198:Kurt Gödel 144:computable 134:arithmetic 126:consistent 67:April 2023 42:references 276:of given 423:, 1988. 343:See also 118:complete 466:(ed.). 437:R. Zach 298:ordinal 288:gave a 286:Gentzen 120:set of 55:improve 320:Tarski 122:axioms 102:German 44:, but 462:. In 244:and 254:all 207:all 92:In 483:: 427:. 377:, 136:. 96:, 472:. 447:. 303:0 301:ε 280:. 80:) 74:( 69:) 65:( 51:. 20:)

Index

Hilbert's Program
references
inline citations
improve
introducing
Learn how and when to remove this message
mathematics
German
David Hilbert
foundational crisis of mathematics
foundations of mathematics
complete
axioms
consistent
real analysis
arithmetic
Gödel's incompleteness theorems
computable
formal language
uncountable
Decidability
Gödel's incompleteness theorems
Kurt Gödel
Peano arithmetic
computably enumerable
Entscheidungsproblem
mathematical logic
proof theory
reverse mathematics
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑