Knowledge (XXG)

Philosophy of desire

Source 📝

498:. Cambridge University Press, 1982, page 251: "In the end, the flowing streams of sense-desire must be 'cut' or 'crossed' completely; nevertheless, for the duration of the Path, a monk must perforce work with motivational and perceptual processes as they ordinarily are, that is to say, based on desire ... Thus, during mental training, the stream is not to be 'cut' immediately, but guided, like water along viaducts. The meditative steadying of the mind by counting in- and out-breaths (in the mindfulness of breathing) is compared to the steadying of a boat in 'a fierce current' by its rudder. The disturbance of the flow of a mountain stream by irrigation channels cut into its sides it used to illustrate the weakening of insight by the 405:. Need is a biological instinct that is articulated in demand, yet demand has a double function, on one hand it articulates need and on the other acts as a demand for love. So, even after the need articulated in demand is satisfied, the demand for love remains unsatisfied and this leftover is desire. For Lacan "desire is neither the appetite for satisfaction nor the demand for love, but the difference that results from the subtraction of the first from the second" (article cited). Desire then is the surplus produced by the articulation of need in demand. Lacan adds that "desire begins to take shape in the margin in which demand becomes separated from need." Hence desire can never be satisfied, or as 394:
in the presence of the other, that desire appears in the full sense of the term." "That the subject should come to recognize and to name his/her desire, that is the efficacious action of analysis. But it is not a question of recognizing something which would be entirely given. In naming it, the subject creates, brings forth, a new presence in the world." "hat is important is to teach the subject to name, to articulate, to bring desire into existence." Now, although the truth about desire is somehow present in discourse, discourse can never articulate the whole truth about desire: whenever discourse attempts to articulate desire, there is always a leftover, a surplus.
321:"For instance, granted that, when I desire my glass of port wine, I have also an idea of the pleasure I expect from it, plainly that pleasure cannot be the only object of my desire; the port wine must be included in my object, else I might be led by my desire to take wormwood instead of wine . . . If the desire is to take a definite direction, it is absolutely necessary that the idea of the object, from which the pleasure is expected, should also be present and should control my activity." 144:
for instance, those originating in the body, such as the desire for nourishment, namely hunger and thirst, and a separate kind of desire answering to each kind of nourishment; and the desires connected with taste and sex and sensations of touch in general; and those of smell, hearing, and vision. Rational desires are those which we are induced to have; there are many things we desire to see or get because we have been told of them and induced to believe them good.
313:"In the first place, plainly, we are not always conscious of expecting pleasure, when we desire a thing. We may only be conscious of the thing which we desire, and may be impelled to make for it at once, without any calculation as to whether it will bring us pleasure or pain. In the second place, even when we do expect pleasure, it can certainly be very rarely pleasure only which we desire. 212:, alter our level of power or striving: joy is a passage "from a lesser to a greater perfection" or degree of power (III Prop. 11 Schol.), just as sadness is the opposite. Desire, qualified by the imagination and the intellect, is an attempt to maximize power, to "strive to imagine those things that increase or aid the body's power of acting." (III Prop. 12). Spinoza ends the 239:. He says "I can say of every representation that it is at least possible (as a cognition) it should be bound up with a pleasure. Of representation that I call pleasant I say that it actually excites pleasure in me. But the beautiful we think as having a necessary reference to satisfaction." Desire is found in the representation of the object. 393:
and it is central to Lacanian theories. For the aim of the talking cure—psychoanalysis—is precisely to lead the analysis and or patient to uncover the truth about their desire, but this is only possible if that desire is articulated, or spoken. Lacan said that "it is only once it is formulated, named
167:
can represent things that are absent and not only objects at hand. Desire is also the preservation of objects already present, as well as the desire that certain effects not appear, that what affects one adversely be curtailed and prevented in the future. Moral and temporal values attach to desire in
143:
Everything, too, is pleasant for which we have the desire within us, since desire is the craving for pleasure. Of the desires some are irrational, some associated with reason. By irrational I mean those which do not arise from any opinion held by the mind. Of this kind are those known as ‘natural’;
100:
the soul is seen to be involved in motion, because animals desire things and in their desire, they acquire locomotion. Aristotle argued that desire is implicated in animal interactions and the propensity of animals to motion. But Aristotle acknowledges that desire cannot account for all purposive
286:
in de Sade is opposition not to desire but to its spontaneity. Blanchot writes that in Sade, "for passion to become energy, it is necessary that it be constricted, that it be mediated by passing through a necessary moment of insensibility, then it will be the greatest passion possible." Here is
308:
states that pleasure is the sole object of all desire. Mill suggests that a desire for an object is caused by an idea of the possible pleasure that would result from the attainment of the object. The desire is fulfilled when this pleasure is achieved. On this view, the pleasure is the sole
259:) in general." It is in the restless movement of the negative that desire removes the antithesis between itself and its object, "and the object of immediate desire is a living thing," an object that forever remains an independent existence, something other. Hegel's inflection of desire via 123:
does not suggest the dark horse be done away with, since its passions make possible a movement towards the objects of desire, but he qualifies desire and places it in a relation to reason so that the object of desire can be discerned correctly, so that we may have the right desire.
427:
is the object of desire, it is not the object towards which desire tends, but the cause of desire. For desire is not a relation to an object but a relation to a lack (manque). Then desire appears as a social construct since it is always constituted in a dialectical relationship.
20:
has been identified as a recurring philosophical problem. It has been variously interpreted as what compels someone towards the highest state of human nature or consciousness, as well as being posited as either something to be eliminated or a powerful source of potential.
365:
were the first teaching of Gautama Buddha after attaining Nirvana. They state that suffering is an inevitable part of life as we know it. The cause of this suffering is attachment to, or craving for worldly pleasures of all kinds and clinging to this very existence, our
416:
It is also important to distinguish between desire and the drives. Even though they both belong to the field of the Other (as opposed to love), desire is one, whereas the drives are many. The drives are the partial manifestations of a single force called desire (see
287:
stoicism, as a form of discipline, through which the passions pass. Blanchot says, "Apathy is the spirit of negation, applied to the man who has chosen to be sovereign." Dispersed, uncontrolled passion does not augment one's creative force but it gets diminished.
309:
motivating factor of the desire. Moore proposes an alternative theory in which an actual pleasure is already present in the desire for the object and that the desire is then for that object and only indirectly for any pleasure that results from attaining it.
195:
declares desire to be "the very essence of man," in the "Definitions of the Affects" at the end of Part III. An early example of desire as an ontological principle, it applies to all things or "modes" in the world, each of which has a particular vital
282:, the libertine is one of a type that sometimes intersects with a Sadean man, who finds in stoicism, solitude, and apathy the proper conditions. Blanchot writes, "the libertine is thoughtful, self-contained, incapable of being moved by just anything." 370:" and the things or people we—due to our delusions—deem the cause of our respective happiness or unhappiness. The suffering ends when the craving and desire ends, or one is freed from all desires by eliminating the delusions, reaches "Enlightenment". 109:, makes it possible for one to apprehend an object of desire, to see it as desirable. In this way reason and desire work together to determine what is a good object of desire. This resonates with desire in the chariots of Plato's 168:
that objects which enhance one's future are considered more desirable than those that do not, and it introduces the possibility, or even necessity, of postponing desire in anticipation of some future event, anticipating
373:
While greed and lust are always unskillful, desire is ethically variable—it can be skillful, unskillful, or neutral. In the Buddhist perspective, the enemy to be defeated is craving rather than desire in general.
204:(Part III, Proposition 7). Different striving beings have different levels of power, depending on their capacity to persevere in being. Affects, or emotions which are divided into the 361:. Nirvana means "cessation", "extinction" (of suffering) or "extinguished", "quieted", "calmed"; it is also known as "Awakening" or "Enlightenment" in the West. The 229:
suggests that reason is subject to passion. Motion is put into effect by desire, passions, and inclinations. It is desire, along with belief, that motivates action.
453:
has been widely credited as a landmark work tackling philosophical and psychoanalytical conceptions of desire, and proposing a new theory of desire in the form of
71:
to refer to both desire as a broad category and as a specific kind of desire. Aristotle clarifies the varying notions by specifying that overarching category is
119:
the soul is guided by two horses, a dark horse of passion and a white horse of reason. Here passion and reason, as in Aristotle, are also together.
216:
by a proposition that both moral virtue and spiritual blessedness are a direct result of essential power to exist, i.e. desire (Part V Prop. 42).
163:
writes of the passion of desire as an agitation of the soul that projects desire, for what it represents as agreeable, into the future. Desire in
741: 708: 688: 668: 683:"...what is important is to teach the subject to name, to articulate, to bring desire into existence" (W. W. Norton & Company, 1991), 811: 179: 242: 174: 317:
On Moore's view, Mill's theory is too non-specific as to the objects of desire. Moore provides the following example:
647:
David Burton, "Buddhism, Knowledge and Liberation: A Philosophical Study." Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2004, page 22.
221: 38:
argued that individual desires must be postponed in the name of a higher ideal. Similarly, within the teachings of
701:
The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: Book II: The Ego in Freud's Theory and in the Technique of Psychoanalysis 1954-1955
516: 402: 357:
that one experiences in human existence. The extinction of this craving leads one to ultimate happiness, or
247: 628: 571: 457:. Deleuze and Guattari regard desire as a productive force, not as originating from lack like Lacan does. 512: 791: 476: 133: 54:). While on the path to liberation, a practitioner is advised to "generate desire" for skillful ends. 786:
Mixing memories and desire. Postmodern erotics of writing in the speculative fiction of Angela Carter
756: 585: 235: 155: 29: 816: 111: 342: 329:, following desires (like passions or in Fourier's own words 'attractions') is a means to attain 406: 737: 704: 684: 664: 550: 444: 362: 160: 779:
Resexualizing the desexualized. The language of desire and erotic love in the classic of odes
612: 598: 542: 367: 305: 292: 275: 187: 413:
is not to realize its goal, to find full satisfaction, but to reproduce itself as desire."
632: 499: 437: 418: 326: 264: 252: 454: 440: 192: 805: 423: 382: 230: 169: 164: 350: 136:. Appetition, or appetite, is a longing for or seeking after something; a craving. 43: 761: 449: 46:, identified as the most potent form of desire, is thought to be the cause of all 297: 106: 271:
in this view has a negative attitude towards "otherness, to desire, and work."
301: 226: 554: 125: 91: 681:
The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: Book I: Freud's Papers on Technique 1953-1954
546: 101:
movement towards a goal. He brackets the problem by positing that perhaps
471: 346: 300:
argued that two theories of desire should be clearly distinguished. The
268: 260: 120: 96: 39: 35: 358: 330: 51: 530: 466: 354: 283: 102: 47: 796:
The Aesthetics of Desire and Surprise: Phenomenology and Speculation
251:
with the assertion that "self-consciousness is the state of desire (
25: 569:
Lieber, Francis; Wigglesworth, Edward; Bradford, T. G. (1832).
233:
establishes a relation between the beautiful and pleasure in
643: 641: 625: 496:
Selfless Persons: Thought and Imagery in Theravada Buddhism
263:
becomes important in understanding desire as it appears in
50:, which can be eliminated to attain greater happiness ( 736:. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 251. 661:
The Lacanian Subject: Between Language and Jouissance
719:Lacan, J., 'The Signification of the Phallus' in 419:The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis 200:(sometimes expressed with the Latin "conatus") 105:, in conjunction with desire and by way of the 732:Schrift, Alan D. (2017). Audi, Robert (ed.). 8: 139:Aristotle makes the distinction as follows: 128:distinguishes desire into two aspects of 401:Lacan distinguishes desire from need and 765:, 1972, pp. 93, 115, 322–333, 354, 400. 655: 653: 529:Moss, Jessica; Schwab, Whitney (2019). 487: 734:The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy 7: 703:(W. W. Norton & Company, 1991), 663:(Princeton University Press, 1996), 535:Journal of the History of Philosophy 245:begins his exposition of desire in 588:1370a18-27, trans. W. Rhys Roberts 353:is thought to be the cause of all 14: 399:The Signification of the Phallus 635:dictionary with à€šà€żà€°à„à€”à€š as input 79:is a type of desire along with 1: 278:in this regard, in his essay 243:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 175:Beyond the Pleasure Principle 567:"Peripatetic philosophy" in 421:"). If one can surmise that 389:follows Freud's concept of 833: 222:A Treatise on Human Nature 781:, Fabrizio Serra Editore. 513:"The Wings to Awakening," 436:French philosophers and 341:Within the teachings of 75:. Within that category, 812:Propositional attitudes 248:Phenomenology of Spirit 202:to persist in existence 798:, Lexington Books 2015 572:Encyclopedia Americana 323: 315: 296:, British philosopher 256: 792:Jadranka Skorin-Kapov 547:10.1353/hph.2019.0000 531:"The Birth of Belief" 477:Passions (philosophy) 319: 311: 87:(spirited thinking). 784:Nicolosi M. Grazia, 757:Deleuze and Guattari 511:Thanissaro Bhikkhu, 432:Deleuze and Guattari 236:Critique of Judgment 156:Passions of the Soul 149:Western philosophers 67:Plato uses the term 777:Middendorf Ulrike, 515:. See specifically 631:2017-08-17 at the 438:critical theorists 409:puts it "desire's 343:Siddhartha Gautama 180:pleasure principle 743:978-1-107-64379-6 709:978-0-393-30709-2 689:978-0-393-30697-2 669:978-0-691-01589-7 616:(1903), pp. 70-71 500:five 'hindrances' 363:Four Noble Truths 824: 766: 754: 748: 747: 729: 723: 717: 711: 697: 691: 677: 671: 657: 648: 645: 636: 623: 617: 613:Principia Ethica 609: 603: 599:Principia Ethica 595: 589: 583: 577: 576: 565: 559: 558: 526: 520: 509: 503: 494:Steven Collins, 492: 306:John Stuart Mill 293:Principia Ethica 276:Maurice Blanchot 178:. See also, the 832: 831: 827: 826: 825: 823: 822: 821: 802: 801: 774: 772:Further reading 769: 755: 751: 744: 731: 730: 726: 718: 714: 698: 694: 678: 674: 658: 651: 646: 639: 633:Wayback Machine 624: 620: 610: 606: 596: 592: 584: 580: 575:. Vol. 10. 568: 566: 562: 528: 527: 523: 510: 506: 493: 489: 485: 463: 434: 380: 339: 327:Charles Fourier 265:Marquis de Sade 182:in psychology. 151: 65: 60: 16:In philosophy, 12: 11: 5: 830: 828: 820: 819: 814: 804: 803: 800: 799: 789: 782: 773: 770: 768: 767: 749: 742: 724: 712: 692: 672: 649: 637: 626:spokensanskrit 618: 604: 590: 578: 560: 521: 504: 486: 484: 481: 480: 479: 474: 469: 462: 459: 455:schizoanalysis 445:FĂ©lix Guattari 441:Gilles Deleuze 433: 430: 379: 378:Psychoanalysis 376: 338: 335: 193:Baruch Spinoza 161:RenĂ© Descartes 150: 147: 146: 145: 64: 63:Ancient Greece 61: 59: 56: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 829: 818: 815: 813: 810: 809: 807: 797: 793: 790: 787: 783: 780: 776: 775: 771: 764: 763: 758: 753: 750: 745: 739: 735: 728: 725: 722: 716: 713: 710: 706: 702: 696: 693: 690: 686: 682: 676: 673: 670: 666: 662: 659:Fink, Bruce, 656: 654: 650: 644: 642: 638: 634: 630: 627: 622: 619: 615: 614: 608: 605: 602:(1903), p. 70 601: 600: 594: 591: 587: 582: 579: 574: 573: 564: 561: 556: 552: 548: 544: 540: 536: 532: 525: 522: 518: 514: 508: 505: 501: 497: 491: 488: 482: 478: 475: 473: 470: 468: 465: 464: 460: 458: 456: 452: 451: 447:'s 1972 book 446: 442: 439: 431: 429: 426: 425: 424:objet petit a 420: 414: 412: 411:raison d'ĂȘtre 408: 404: 400: 395: 392: 388: 384: 383:Jacques Lacan 377: 375: 371: 369: 364: 360: 356: 352: 348: 344: 336: 334: 332: 328: 322: 318: 314: 310: 307: 303: 299: 295: 294: 288: 285: 281: 280:Sade's Reason 277: 272: 270: 266: 262: 258: 254: 250: 249: 244: 240: 238: 237: 232: 231:Immanuel Kant 228: 224: 223: 217: 215: 211: 207: 203: 199: 194: 190: 189: 183: 181: 177: 176: 171: 170:Sigmund Freud 166: 165:Immanuel Kant 162: 158: 157: 148: 142: 141: 140: 137: 135: 131: 127: 122: 118: 115:, for in the 114: 113: 108: 104: 99: 98: 93: 88: 86: 82: 78: 74: 70: 62: 57: 55: 53: 49: 45: 41: 37: 33: 32: 27: 22: 19: 795: 785: 778: 762:Anti-Oedipus 760: 752: 733: 727: 720: 715: 700: 695: 680: 675: 660: 621: 611: 607: 597: 593: 581: 570: 563: 538: 534: 524: 517:this section 507: 495: 490: 450:Anti-Oedipus 448: 435: 422: 415: 410: 407:Slavoj ĆœiĆŸek 398: 396: 390: 386: 381: 372: 340: 324: 320: 316: 312: 291: 289: 279: 273: 246: 241: 234: 220: 218: 213: 209: 205: 201: 197: 186: 184: 173: 154: 152: 138: 129: 116: 110: 95: 89: 84: 80: 76: 72: 68: 66: 31:The Republic 30: 23: 17: 15: 699:Lacan, J., 679:Lacan, J., 298:G. E. Moore 107:imagination 83:(wish) and 817:Motivation 806:Categories 483:References 304:theory of 302:hedonistic 227:David Hume 198:"striving" 130:appetition 555:1538-4586 541:(1): 11. 355:suffering 126:Aristotle 92:Aristotle 77:epithumia 69:epithumia 48:suffering 788:, CUECM. 629:Archived 586:Rhetoric 472:Hedonism 461:See also 347:Buddhism 337:Buddhism 274:Reading 269:Stoicism 261:stoicism 257:Begierde 208:and the 172:'s text 134:volition 121:Socrates 117:Phaedrus 112:Phaedrus 97:De Anima 81:boulĂȘsis 40:Buddhism 36:Socrates 359:Nirvana 351:craving 331:harmony 290:In his 185:In his 58:History 52:Nirvana 44:craving 740:  721:Écrits 707:  687:  667:  553:  467:Desire 403:demand 391:Wunsch 284:Apathy 253:German 214:Ethics 206:joyful 188:Ethics 132:, and 103:reason 85:thumos 73:orexis 18:desire 387:dĂ©sir 26:Plato 738:ISBN 705:ISBN 685:ISBN 665:ISBN 551:ISSN 443:and 368:self 325:For 543:doi 397:In 385:'s 349:), 219:In 210:sad 153:In 94:'s 90:In 28:'s 24:In 808:: 794:, 759:, 652:^ 640:^ 549:. 539:57 537:. 533:. 502:." 333:. 267:. 255:: 225:, 191:, 159:, 42:, 34:, 746:. 557:. 545:: 519:. 417:" 366:" 345:(

Index

Plato
The Republic
Socrates
Buddhism
craving
suffering
Nirvana
Aristotle
De Anima
reason
imagination
Phaedrus
Socrates
Aristotle
volition
Passions of the Soul
René Descartes
Immanuel Kant
Sigmund Freud
Beyond the Pleasure Principle
pleasure principle
Ethics
Baruch Spinoza
A Treatise on Human Nature
David Hume
Immanuel Kant
Critique of Judgment
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
Phenomenology of Spirit
German

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑