Knowledge

Reductio ad absurdum

Source 📝

33: 935: 183:'s attribution of human faults to the gods, Xenophanes states that humans also believe that the gods' bodies have human form. But if horses and oxen could draw, they would draw the gods with horse and ox bodies. The gods cannot have both forms, so this is a contradiction. Therefore, the attribution of other human characteristics to the gods, such as human faults, is also false. 227:. Typically, Socrates' opponent would make what would seem to be an innocuous assertion. In response, Socrates, via a step-by-step train of reasoning, bringing in other background assumptions, would make the person admit that the assertion resulted in an absurd or contradictory conclusion, forcing him to abandon his assertion and adopt a position of 353:
In 13.5, Nagarjuna wishes to demonstrate consequences of the presumption that things essentially, or inherently, exist, pointing out that if a "young man" exists in himself then it follows he cannot grow old (because he would no longer be a "young man"). As we attempt to separate the man from his
94:
and has been used throughout history in both formal mathematical and philosophical reasoning, as well as in debate. Formally, the proof technique is captured by an axiom for "Reductio ad Absurdum", normally given the abbreviation RAA, which is expressible in
432:) cannot both be true. Therefore, if a proposition and its negation can both be derived logically from a premise, it can be concluded that the premise is false. This technique, known as indirect proof or 354:
properties (youth), we find that everything is subject to momentary change, and are left with nothing beyond the merely arbitrary convention that such entities as "young man" depend upon.
267:, where it was argued that if 1,000,000 grains of sand formed a heap, and removing one grain from a heap left it a heap, then a single grain of sand (or even no grains) forms a heap. 426: 403: 981: 87:, is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absurdity or contradiction. 976: 905: 953: 878: 515: 915: 888: 718: 655: 127:
The Earth cannot be flat; otherwise, since the Earth is assumed to be finite in extent, we would find people falling off the edge.
105:) and it is sometimes named to make this connection clear. It is a consequence of the related mathematical proof technique called 138:
The first example argues that denial of the premise would result in a ridiculous conclusion, against the evidence of our senses (
532:
Pasti, Mary. Reductio Ad Absurdum: An Exercise in the Study of Population Change. United States, Cornell University, Jan., 1977.
314:) of any essential existence. Nāgārjuna's main goal is often seen by scholars as refuting the essentialism of certain Buddhist 971: 382: 347: 295: 735: 535:
Daigle, Robert W.. The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument Prior to Aristotle. N.p., San Jose State University, 1991.
306:
arguments are used to show that any theory of substance or essence was unsustainable and therefore, phenomena (
91: 939: 433: 195: 172: 143: 107: 471: 461: 101: 32: 191: 996: 986: 279: 256: 96: 685: 576: 991: 476: 456: 218: 146:(also known as an indirect proof), which argues that the denial of the premise would result in a 139: 787: 319: 911: 884: 714: 814: 408: 162: 510: 264: 240: 224: 131: 299: 600: 552: 385:, which states that a proposition cannot be both true and false. That is, a proposition 486: 466: 388: 245: 934: 506: 965: 147: 46: 17: 761: 283: 629: 134:
because such a number would have to not be divisible by two, which is impossible.
709:
Howard-Snyder, Frances; Howard-Snyder, Daniel; Wasserman, Ryan (30 March 2012).
335: 42: 481: 315: 276: 176: 491: 381:
Aristotle clarified the connection between contradiction and falsity in his
235: 150:(there is a "smallest" number and yet there is a number smaller than it). 326: 206: 228: 948: 794:. Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Clark University 443: 331: 202: 180: 78: 66: 54: 31: 310:) such as change, causality, and sense perception were empty ( 249: 244:
where he referred to it as demonstration to the impossible (
123:
argument can take a range of forms, as these examples show:
186:
Greek mathematicians proved fundamental propositions using
338:
schools which posited a theory of ontological substances (
855:
New York: Columibia University Press. 2005, pgs. 225-263.
171:
argument can be found in a satirical poem attributed to
99:. This axiom is the introduction rule for negation (see 736:"The reductio ad absurdum argument prior to Aristotle" 411: 391: 605:
Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged
821:. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 198:(c. 287 – c. 212 BCE) are two very early examples. 904:Ferguson, Thomas Macaulay; Priest, Graham (2016). 762:"Reductio ad Absurdum - Definition & Examples" 420: 397: 263:Another example of this technique is found in the 372:And because an old man does not grow old either. 260: "demonstration to the impossible", 62b). 713:(5th ed.). McGraw-Hill Higher Education. 234:The technique was also a focus of the work of 69:for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as 8: 839: 437: 216: 210: 166: 71: 59: 36: 215:arguments to a formal dialectical method ( 205:(424–348 BCE), relating the discourses of 27:Argument that leads to a logical absurdity 410: 390: 910:. Oxford University Press. p. 146. 864: 526:The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way 142:). The second example is a mathematical 634:The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 544: 505:Hyde, Dominic; Raffman, Diana (2018). 369:Because a young man does not grow old. 330:(essential nature) and also the Hindu 286:ideas have absurd conclusions through 194:(mid-4th – mid-3rd centuries BCE) and 623: 621: 294:, "consequence" in Sanskrit). In the 7: 679: 677: 675: 577:"Definition of REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM" 366:Something different does not change. 345: 954:Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 819:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 516:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 442:arguments in formal fields such as 238:(384–322 BCE), particularly in his 686:"Reductio Ad Absurdum in Argument" 412: 90:This argument form traces back to 25: 528:, Oxford: Oxford University Press 933: 81:for "argument to absurdity") or 982:Theorems in propositional logic 660:A Concise Introduction to Logic 363:A thing itself does not change. 282:centers on showing how various 654:DeLancey, Craig (2017-03-27), 553:"Reductio ad absurdum | logic" 383:principle of non-contradiction 377:Principle of non-contradiction 130:There is no smallest positive 1: 938:The dictionary definition of 119:The "absurd" conclusion of a 877:Ziembiński, Zygmunt (2013). 324:) which posited theories of 165:. The earliest example of a 977:Latin philosophical phrases 788:"Euclid's Elements: Book I" 251:ἡ εἰς τὸ ἀδύνατον ἀπόδειξις 1013: 734:Daigle, Robert W. (1991). 436:, has formed the basis of 250: 813:Bobzien, Susanne (2006). 656:"8. Reductio ad Absurdum" 524:Garfield, Jay L. (1995), 346:Example from Nāgārjuna's 201:The earlier dialogues of 883:. Springer. p. 95. 92:Ancient Greek philosophy 840:Hyde & Raffman 2018 581:www.merriam-webster.com 557:Encyclopedia Britannica 519:(Summer 2018 ed.). 421:{\displaystyle \lnot Q} 949:"Reductio ad absurdum" 630:"Reductio ad absurdum" 607:(12th ed.), 2014 601:"reductio ad absurdum" 438: 434:proof by contradiction 422: 399: 217: 211: 196:Archimedes of Syracuse 173:Xenophanes of Colophon 167: 144:proof by contradiction 108:proof by contradiction 73:argumentum ad absurdum 72: 60: 50: 37: 972:Latin logical phrases 907:A Dictionary of Logic 853:Nagarjuna in Context. 786:Joyce, David (1996). 742:. San Jose State Univ 662:, Open SUNY Textbooks 472:List of Latin phrases 462:Argument from fallacy 423: 400: 148:logical contradiction 102:negation introduction 35: 18:Reductio ad absurdium 684:Nordquist, Richard. 439:reductio ad absurdum 409: 389: 348:Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 304:reductio ad absurdum 296:Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 290:arguments (known as 288:reductio ad absurdum 209:, raised the use of 192:Euclid of Alexandria 188:reductio ad absurdum 161:was used throughout 159:Reductio ad absurdum 121:reductio ad absurdum 84:apagogical arguments 61:reductio ad absurdum 38:Reductio ad absurdum 280:Buddhist philosophy 271:Buddhist philosophy 223:), also called the 97:propositional logic 711:The Power of Logic 628:Nicholas Rescher. 477:Mathematical proof 457:Appeal to ridicule 418: 395: 140:empirical evidence 51: 792:Euclid's Elements 507:"Sorites Paradox" 446:and mathematics. 405:and its negation 398:{\displaystyle Q} 259: 175:(c. 570 – c. 475 45:exhibited at the 16:(Redirected from 1004: 958: 937: 922: 921: 901: 895: 894: 874: 868: 862: 856: 851:Wasler, Joseph. 849: 843: 837: 831: 830: 828: 826: 810: 804: 803: 801: 799: 783: 777: 776: 774: 773: 766:Literary Devices 758: 752: 751: 749: 747: 731: 725: 724: 706: 700: 699: 697: 696: 681: 670: 669: 668: 667: 651: 645: 644: 642: 640: 625: 616: 615: 614: 612: 597: 591: 590: 588: 587: 573: 567: 566: 564: 563: 549: 529: 520: 511:Zalta, Edward N. 441: 427: 425: 424: 419: 404: 402: 401: 396: 318:schools (mainly 255: 253: 252: 222: 214: 170: 163:Greek philosophy 154:Greek philosophy 75: 63: 40: 21: 1012: 1011: 1007: 1006: 1005: 1003: 1002: 1001: 962: 961: 947: 941:per impossibile 930: 925: 918: 903: 902: 898: 891: 880:Practical Logic 876: 875: 871: 863: 859: 850: 846: 838: 834: 824: 822: 815:"Ancient Logic" 812: 811: 807: 797: 795: 785: 784: 780: 771: 769: 760: 759: 755: 745: 743: 740:Master's Thesis 733: 732: 728: 721: 708: 707: 703: 694: 692: 683: 682: 673: 665: 663: 653: 652: 648: 638: 636: 627: 626: 619: 610: 608: 599: 598: 594: 585: 583: 575: 574: 570: 561: 559: 551: 550: 546: 542: 523: 504: 501: 496: 452: 407: 406: 387: 386: 379: 360: 351: 273: 265:sorites paradox 241:Prior Analytics 225:Socratic method 179:). Criticizing 156: 132:rational number 117: 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 1010: 1008: 1000: 999: 994: 989: 984: 979: 974: 964: 963: 960: 959: 945: 929: 928:External links 926: 924: 923: 917:978-0192511553 916: 896: 890:978-9401756044 889: 869: 867:, p. 210. 857: 844: 832: 805: 778: 753: 726: 720:978-0078038198 719: 701: 671: 646: 617: 592: 568: 543: 541: 538: 537: 536: 533: 530: 521: 500: 497: 495: 494: 489: 487:Slippery slope 484: 479: 474: 469: 467:Contraposition 464: 459: 453: 451: 448: 417: 414: 394: 378: 375: 374: 373: 370: 367: 364: 359: 356: 350: 344: 272: 269: 155: 152: 136: 135: 128: 116: 113: 41:, painting by 26: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1009: 998: 995: 993: 990: 988: 985: 983: 980: 978: 975: 973: 970: 969: 967: 956: 955: 950: 946: 944:at Wiktionary 943: 942: 936: 932: 931: 927: 919: 913: 909: 908: 900: 897: 892: 886: 882: 881: 873: 870: 866: 865:Garfield 1995 861: 858: 854: 848: 845: 841: 836: 833: 820: 816: 809: 806: 793: 789: 782: 779: 767: 763: 757: 754: 741: 737: 730: 727: 722: 716: 712: 705: 702: 691: 687: 680: 678: 676: 672: 661: 657: 650: 647: 635: 631: 624: 622: 618: 606: 602: 596: 593: 582: 578: 572: 569: 558: 554: 548: 545: 539: 534: 531: 527: 522: 518: 517: 512: 508: 503: 502: 498: 493: 490: 488: 485: 483: 480: 478: 475: 473: 470: 468: 465: 463: 460: 458: 455: 454: 449: 447: 445: 440: 435: 431: 415: 392: 384: 376: 371: 368: 365: 362: 361: 357: 355: 349: 343: 341: 337: 333: 329: 328: 323: 322: 317: 313: 309: 305: 301: 297: 293: 289: 285: 281: 278: 270: 268: 266: 261: 258: 247: 243: 242: 237: 232: 230: 226: 221: 220: 213: 208: 204: 199: 197: 193: 189: 184: 182: 178: 174: 169: 164: 160: 153: 151: 149: 145: 141: 133: 129: 126: 125: 124: 122: 114: 112: 110: 109: 104: 103: 98: 93: 88: 86: 85: 80: 76: 74: 68: 64: 62: 56: 48: 47:Royal Academy 44: 39: 34: 30: 19: 952: 940: 906: 899: 879: 872: 860: 852: 847: 835: 823:. Retrieved 818: 808: 798:December 23, 796:. Retrieved 791: 781: 770:. Retrieved 768:. 2014-05-18 765: 756: 744:. Retrieved 739: 729: 710: 704: 693:. Retrieved 689: 664:, retrieved 659: 649: 637:. Retrieved 633: 609:, retrieved 604: 595: 584:. Retrieved 580: 571: 560:. Retrieved 556: 547: 525: 514: 429: 380: 352: 339: 325: 320: 311: 307: 303: 291: 287: 284:essentialist 274: 262: 239: 233: 200: 187: 185: 158: 157: 137: 120: 118: 106: 100: 89: 83: 82: 70: 58: 52: 29: 611:October 29, 43:John Pettie 997:Pyrrhonism 987:Madhyamaka 966:Categories 825:August 22, 772:2021-08-31 746:August 22, 695:2019-11-27 666:2021-08-31 586:2019-11-27 562:2019-11-27 540:References 482:Prasangika 321:Vaibhasika 316:Abhidharma 277:Madhyamaka 992:Arguments 690:ThoughtCo 413:¬ 340:dravyatas 336:Vaiśeṣika 300:Nāgārjuna 236:Aristotle 492:Strawman 450:See also 327:svabhava 292:prasaṅga 275:Much of 219:elenchus 212:reductio 207:Socrates 168:reductio 115:Examples 639:21 July 513:(ed.). 499:Sources 308:dharmas 49:in 1884 914:  887:  717:  229:aporia 509:. In 444:logic 428:(not- 332:Nyāya 312:sunya 246:Greek 203:Plato 181:Homer 79:Latin 67:Latin 55:logic 912:ISBN 885:ISBN 827:2012 800:2017 748:2012 715:ISBN 641:2009 613:2016 358:13:5 334:and 257:lit. 342:). 302:'s 231:. 177:BCE 111:. 53:In 968:: 951:. 817:. 790:. 764:. 738:. 688:. 674:^ 658:, 632:. 620:^ 603:, 579:. 555:. 298:, 254:, 248:: 190:. 57:, 957:. 920:. 893:. 842:. 829:. 802:. 775:. 750:. 723:. 698:. 643:. 589:. 565:. 430:Q 416:Q 393:Q 77:( 65:( 20:)

Index

Reductio ad absurdium
A bearded white Christian cleric in red argues towards an older pensive white Christian cleric in black.
John Pettie
Royal Academy
logic
Latin
Latin
Ancient Greek philosophy
propositional logic
negation introduction
proof by contradiction
rational number
empirical evidence
proof by contradiction
logical contradiction
Greek philosophy
Xenophanes of Colophon
BCE
Homer
Euclid of Alexandria
Archimedes of Syracuse
Plato
Socrates
elenchus
Socratic method
aporia
Aristotle
Prior Analytics
Greek
lit.

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.