Knowledge (XXG)

Syntactic ambiguity

Source đź“ť

118:
Global ambiguities are often unnoticed because readers tend to choose the interpretation they understand to be more probable. One example of a global ambiguity is "The woman held the baby in the green blanket." In this example, the baby, incidentally wrapped in the green blanket, is being held by the woman, or the woman is using the green blanket as an instrument to hold the baby, or the woman is wrapped in the green blanket and holding the baby.
651:
As children read and interpret syntactically ambiguous sentences, the speed at which initial syntactic commitments are made is lower in children than in adults. Furthermore, children appear to be less skilled at directing their attention back to the part of the sentence that is most informative in terms of aiding reanalysis. Other evidence attributes differences in interpreting ambiguous sentences to
621:
and the princess respectively. Thus, the readers are forced to reanalyse and their reading times will therefore rise. In sentence 1, however, the ambiguity of the reflexive pronoun “herself” fits both the maid and the princess. This means the readers do not have to reanalyse. Thus, ambiguous sentences will take a shorter time to read compared to clarified ones.
680:. For high reading span subjects who had the best verbal working memory, they were overall faster than the low reading span subjects. Within the high reading span subjects, however, they responded faster to inanimate subjects and took longer to respond to animate subjects. This was because the animate subjects had a greater propensity to create a 655:
span. While adults tend to have a higher working memory span, they sometimes spend more time resolving the ambiguity but tend to be more accurate in their final interpretation. Children, in contrast, can decide quickly on an interpretation because they consider only the interpretations their working
633:
The good-enough approach to understanding language claims that representations of meaning are usually incomplete and language processing only partial. A good-enough interpretation may occur when such a representation is not robust, supported by context, or both and must handle potentially distracting
558:
According to the reanalysis model, processing is hard once the reader has realised that their analysis is false (with respect to the already adopted syntactic structure) and he or she must then return and recheck the structure. Most reanalysis models, like the unrestricted race model, work in series,
544:
Competition-based models hold that differing syntactic analyses rival each other when syntactic ambiguities are resolved. If probability and language constraints offer similar support for each one, especially strong competition occurs. On the other hand, when constraints support one analysis over the
650:
differently from adults due to lack of experience. Children have not yet learned how the environment and contextual clues can suggest a certain interpretation of a sentence. They have also not yet developed the ability to acknowledge that ambiguous words and phrases can be interpreted multiple ways.
620:
Research showed that people took less time to read persistently ambiguous sentences (sentence 1) than temporarily ambiguous sentences that were clarified later (sentences 2 and 3). In sentences 2 and 3, the reflexive pronouns “himself” and “herself” clarify that “who scratched” is modifying the son
600:
However, the name "unrestricted race" comes directly from its properties taken from the constraint-based models. As in constraint-based theories, any source of information can support the different analyses of an ambiguous structure; thus the name. In the model, the other possible structures of an
117:
A globally ambiguous sentence is one that has at least two distinct interpretations and where reading the entire sentence does not resolve the ambiguity. Globally ambiguous sentences exist where no feature of the representation (i.e. word order) distinguishes the possible distinct interpretations.
624:
This is called the underspecification account as readers do not stick to a meaning when not provided with clarifying words. The reader understands someone scratched herself but does not seek to determine whether it was the maid or the princess. This is also known as the “good-enough” approach to
579:
Research supports the reanalysis model as the most likely reason for why interpreting these ambiguous sentences is hard. Results of many experiments tracking the eye-movements of subjects have demonstrated that it is just as hard to process a persistently ambiguous sentence (1) as an unambiguous
549:
sentences are easier to process than disambiguated (clearer) sentences, showing that the analyses do not compete against each other in the former. Plausibility tends to strengthen one analysis and eliminate rivalry. However, the model has not been completely rejected. Some theories claim that
687:(not despite) greater verbal working memory. This suggested that since the low reading span subjects had less cognitive resources, only syntactic cues could be processed while high reading span subjects had more cognitive resources and could thus get tripped up with the garden path sentence. 492:
Significantly enough, structural ambiguities may also be intentionally created when one understands the kinds of syntactic structures that will lead to ambiguity; however, for the respective interpretations to work, they must be compatible with semantic and pragmatic contextual factors.
596:
and Pickering plainly refer to the unrestricted race model as a two-stage reanalysis model. Unlike constraint-based theories, only one analysis can be made at any one time. Thus, reanalysis may sometimes be necessary if information following the first analysis proves it wrong.
530:
employs the term "amphiboly" in a sense of his own, as he has done in the case of other philosophical words. He means it as a confusion of pure understanding with perceived experience, and an attribution to the latter of what belongs only to the former.
545:
other, competition is weak and processing is easy. After van Gompel et al.'s experiments (2005), the reanalysis model has become favoured over competition-based models. Convincing evidence against competition-based models includes the fact that
379:... if one combines the words 'to write-while-not-writing': for then it means, that he has the power to write and not to write at once; whereas if one does not combine them, it means that when he is not writing he has the power to write. 601:
ambiguous sentence compete in a race, with the structure that is constructed fastest being used. The more such an analysis is supported, and the stronger the support is, the more likely this one will be made first.
126:
A locally ambiguous sentence is a sentence that contains an ambiguous phrase but has only one interpretation. The ambiguity in a locally ambiguous sentence briefly stays and is resolved, i.e.,
1118:
van Gompel, Roger P.G.; Pickering, Martin J.; Pearson, Jamie; Liversedge, Simon P.; et al. (4 January 2005). "Evidence against competition during syntactic ambiguity resolution".
839: 486: 1310: 485:: "I shot an elephant in my pajamas. How he got into my pajamas I don't know." Another sentence, which emerged from early 1960s machine translation research, is " 75:. Consequently, a sentence presents as syntactically ambiguous when it permits reasonable derivation of several possible grammatical structures by an observer. 351:
A creature that eats purple people. (This interpretation is confirmed in the lyrics, although whether the creature itself is also purple is never made clear.)
134:, in which a structurally correct sentence is difficult to interpret because one interpretation of the ambiguous region is not the one that makes most sense. 823: 100:, that can represent the ambiguous sentence's meanings. The task of clarifying which meaning is actually intended from among the possibilities is known as 1517: 1991: 475:
Syntactic or structural ambiguities are frequently found in humour and advertising. One enduring joke using an ambiguous modifier is a quip spoken by
724: 1179:
Traxler, Matthew J.; Pickering, Martin J.; Clifton, Charles (1998-11-01). "Adjunct Attachment Is Not a Form of Lexical Ambiguity Resolution".
588:
The unrestricted race model states that analysis is affected before the introduction of ambiguity and affects which meaning is used (based on
1078: 867: 1485: 730: 375:
writes about an influence of ambiguities on arguments and also about this influence depending on either combination or division of words:
1859: 1526: 813:." Proceedings of the 27th annual meeting on Association for Computational Linguistics. Association for Computational Linguistics, 1989. 921: 836: 961: 941: 794: 200: 1266:
Ferreira, Fernanda; Bailey, Karl G.D.; Ferraro, Vittoria (February 2002). "Good-Enough Representations in Language Comprehension".
86:
may be done by courts. Occasionally, claims based on highly improbable interpretations of such ambiguities are dismissed as being
647: 1317: 1946: 1600: 2067: 1941: 1510: 1054: 507:
In syntactic ambiguity, the same sequence of words is interpreted as having different syntactic structures. In contrast, in
426:
by Danny Bloom in the Testy Copy Editors discussion group in August 2009. He based this on the headline "Violinist linked to
207:
in such a way as not to draw blame on themselves, sending this order in Latin which changes meaning depending on where the
1719: 1540: 1070:
Controlled Natural Language: Third International Workshop, CNL 2012, Zurich, Switzerland, August 29-31, 2012, Proceedings
1605: 1404:
Maryellen C. MacDonald; Marcel A. Just (1992). "Working memory constraints on the processing of syntactic ambiguity".
735: 512: 480: 882: 1693: 71:
but rather from the relationships among words and clauses within a sentence, concealing interpretations beneath the
2087: 1749: 1570: 432: 427: 2092: 2042: 1804: 1503: 127: 2152: 2011: 1590: 857: 760: 1068: 707: 216:
Do not be afraid to kill Edward; it is good. (either Edward, killing him, or being afraid to kill him is good)
1490: 436:
regularly reprints such headlines in its "The Lower Case" column, and has collected them in the anthologies "
2147: 1688: 916: 755: 669: 580:
sentence (2 and 3) because information before the ambiguity only weakly leans towards each possible syntax.
339: 318: 2177: 1844: 1814: 1789: 1729: 1628: 1560: 1160: 1127: 60: 2072: 1966: 1931: 1819: 1794: 1638: 1555: 2057: 1864: 1643: 1355: 1004: 718: 681: 415: 204: 131: 87: 64: 1165: 1132: 2142: 2107: 2052: 1996: 1899: 1884: 1854: 1834: 1809: 1678: 1663: 668:
adults who had the worst verbal working memory, they took longer to process the sentences with the
191: 153: 2218: 2208: 2187: 2112: 2082: 2047: 2027: 1956: 1936: 1874: 1869: 1779: 1769: 1754: 1698: 1429: 1291: 508: 196: 826:." Proceedings of The 1st International Conference on Language Resources & Evaluation. 1998. 1447:
Ferreira, Fernanda; Clifton, Charles (1986-06-01). "The independence of syntactic processing".
1344:"Children's and Adults' On-Line Processing of Syntactically Ambiguous Sentences during Reading" 2167: 2122: 2102: 2062: 2001: 1971: 1951: 1744: 1673: 1464: 1421: 1383: 1283: 1245: 1237: 1196: 1074: 957: 937: 863: 790: 745: 701: 696: 665: 2172: 2097: 1986: 1764: 1456: 1413: 1373: 1363: 1275: 1227: 1188: 1137: 186: 148: 430:
blossoms" that Mike O'Connell had posted, asking what such a headline could be called. The
2213: 1976: 1879: 1774: 1739: 859:
Case, Word Order and Prominence: Interacting Cues in Language Production and Comprehension
843: 673: 1044:
Layman E. Allen "Some Uses of Symbolic Logic in Law Practice" 1962J M.U.L.L. 119, at 120;
1491:
Differentiating syntactic ambiguity (structural ambiguity) from other types of ambiguity
1359: 2162: 2157: 2077: 1961: 1839: 1734: 1575: 1378: 1343: 740: 652: 399: 170:, sometimes owing to the alteration of the natural order of words for metrical reasons. 1495: 1095: 1057:" in H.W. Baade (ed.) "Jurimetrics" Basic Books Inc., New York, USA, 1963, 213, at 228 511:
the structure remains the same, but the individual words are interpreted differently.
219:
Do not kill Edward; it is good to fear. (either Edward or killing him is good to fear)
2202: 1849: 1824: 1658: 1460: 1417: 1214:
Swets, Benjamin; Desmet, Timothy; Clifton, Charles; Ferreira, Fernanda (2008-01-01).
527: 259: 79: 17: 1433: 366:
The British forces left behind waffles (the breakfast item) on the Falkland Islands.
2117: 2037: 1904: 1784: 1668: 1648: 1295: 1028: 750: 713: 610:"The maid of the princess who scratched herself in public was terribly humiliated." 516: 476: 464: 445: 1311:"The use of referential context in children's online interpretation of adjectives" 616:"The son of the princess who scratched herself in public was terribly humiliated." 613:"The son of the princess who scratched himself in public was terribly humiliated." 294:
The word of the Lord came to Zechariah, son of Berekiah, son of Iddo, the prophet.
1368: 784: 34:"Amphibology" redirects here. Not to be confused with amphibiology, the study of 2032: 2006: 1889: 1653: 1580: 589: 460: 456: 407: 363:
The British party of the left rambles indecisively about Falkland Island policy.
343: 230: 27:"Structural ambiguity" redirects here. Not to be confused with the ambiguity of 1216:"Underspecification of syntactic ambiguities: Evidence from self-paced reading" 973: 810: 304:... Zechariah, who was the son of Berekiah, who was the son of the prophet Iddo 301:... Zechariah, who was the son of the prophet Berekiah, who was the son of Iddo 298:... the prophet Zechariah, who was the son of Berekiah, who was the son of Iddo 2182: 1829: 1595: 1550: 1545: 1141: 990: 986: 911: 634:
information. Thus, such information is clipped for successful understanding
593: 403: 238: 96: 82:, the interpretation of syntactically ambiguous phrases in statutory texts or 72: 1468: 1287: 1241: 1200: 1981: 1799: 1724: 1703: 1633: 1585: 1565: 1279: 546: 423: 411: 372: 234: 83: 35: 28: 1387: 1249: 1192: 1425: 1894: 1683: 502: 395: 68: 1232: 1215: 94:
refers to the collection of all possible syntactic structures, known as
835:
MacDonald, Maryellen C., Neal J. Pearlmutter, and Mark S. Seidenberg. "
677: 515:
are often designed to be unambiguous so that they can be parsed into a
130:, by the end of the speech. Sometimes, local ambiguities can result in 1005:"Heads you win: The readers' editor on the art of the headline writer" 41:
Sentences with structures permitting multiple possible interpretations
167: 954:
Red tape holds up new bridge, and more flubs from the nation's press
934:
Squad Helps Dog Bite Victim, and other flubs from the nation's press
824:
Building a Japanese parsed corpus while improving the parsing system
1759: 463:
is "French push bottles up German rear"; life imitated art in the
208: 786:
Structural Ambiguity in English: An Applied Grammatical Inventory
559:
which implies that only one analysis can be supported at a time.
1157:
Unrestricted race: A new model of syntactic ambiguity resolution
310:... Zechariah, who was the son of Berekiah and Iddo, the prophet 1499: 1055:
Modern Logic and Judicial Decision Making: A Sketch of One View
450:
Infant Pulled from Wrecked Car Involved in Short Police Pursuit
307:... the prophet Zechariah, who was the son of Berekiah and Iddo 448:
also has an extensive archive of crash blossoms, for example "
898:, April 28, 1982, as quoted by Gloria Cooper, "Mailbag", 550:
competition makes processing difficult, if only briefly.
277:
John saw a man on a mountain which had a telescope on it.
575:"The dog with the woman that had the parasol was brown." 572:"The woman with the dog that had the parasol was brown." 67:. This form of ambiguity is not derived from the varied 63:
to yield multiple interpretations due to its ambiguous
569:"The dog of the woman that had the parasol was brown." 253:
I'm glad I'm a man, and Lola is also glad to be a man.
1155:
van Gompel, Roger P.G.; Pickering, Martin J. (2000),
283:
John, on a mountain and using a telescope, saw a man.
837:
The lexical nature of syntactic ambiguity resolution
811:
The structure of shared forests in ambiguous parsing
250:
I'm glad I'm a man, and I'm also glad Lola is a man.
2135: 2020: 1924: 1917: 1712: 1621: 1614: 1533: 1342:Holly S. S. L. Joseph; Simon P. Liversedge (2013). 487:
Time flies like an arrow; fruit flies like a banana
286:
John, on a mountain, saw a man who had a telescope.
856:Monique Lamers; Peter de Swart (20 October 2011). 384:Aristotle, Sophistical refutations, Book I, Part 4 270:John saw the man on the mountain with a telescope. 280:John saw a man on a mountain who had a telescope. 274:John, using a telescope, saw a man on a mountain. 1992:Segmented discourse representation theory (SDRT) 467:headline "Eighth Army Push Bottles Up Germans". 377: 1067:Tobias Kuhn; Norbert E Fuchs (9 August 2012). 592:) before multiple analyses can be introduced. 258:The ambiguity is intentional and alludes to a 1511: 660:Low reading span vs. high reading span adults 8: 1486:A detailed discussion of syntactic ambiguity 1268:Current Directions in Psychological Science 1096:A Dictionary of English Philosophical Terms 247:I'm glad I'm a man, and Lola is also a man. 178: 144:The duke yet lives that Henry shall depose. 1921: 1618: 1518: 1504: 1496: 846:." Psychological review 101.4 (1994): 676. 180:Eduardum occidere nolite timere bonum est. 59:, is characterized by the potential for a 1377: 1367: 1231: 1164: 1131: 1113: 1111: 1109: 1107: 1105: 862:. Springer Science & Business Media. 359:British Left Waffles on Falkland Islands. 778: 776: 789:. Vol. 2 vols. London: Continuum. 772: 725:Ibis redibis nunquam per bella peribis 648:Children interpret ambiguous sentences 459:or recycled. One celebrated one from 1947:Discourse representation theory (DRT) 1399: 1397: 1261: 1259: 822:Kurohashi, Sadao, and Makoto Nagao. " 7: 731:List of linguistic example sentences 322:, the title of a comedy-horror film 1860:Quantificational variability effect 1527:Formal semantics (natural language) 809:Billot, Sylvie, and Bernard Lang. " 348:A purple creature that eats people. 244:Lola and I are both glad I'm a man. 227:I'm glad I'm a man, and so is Lola. 1033:What The Papers Didn't Mean to Say 605:Consider the following statements: 455:Many purported crash blossoms are 331:Lesbian vampires that are killers. 25: 914:, "On Language: Crash Blossoms", 563:Consider the following statements 422:was proposed for these ambiguous 201:Roger Mortimer, 1st Earl of March 1053:L.E. Allen & M.E. Caldwell " 497:Syntactic and semantic ambiguity 1309:Yi Ting Huang; Jesse Snedeker. 166:Amphiboly occurs frequently in 1942:Combinatory categorial grammar 1449:Journal of Memory and Language 1181:Journal of Memory and Language 1120:Journal of Memory and Language 1: 1720:Antecedent-contained deletion 1093:adapted from Garden, Francis 1035:Scouse Press, Liverpool, 1965 678:inanimate or animate subjects 442:Red Tape Holds Up New Bridge" 203:supposedly plotted to murder 1461:10.1016/0749-596X(86)90006-9 1418:10.1016/0010-0285(92)90003-K 1369:10.1371/journal.pone.0054141 513:Controlled natural languages 438:Squad Helps Dog Bite Victim" 328:Killers of lesbian vampires. 90:and without merit. The term 69:meanings of individual words 736:Natural language processing 676:and had similar times from 325:Lesbians who kill vampires. 161:The duke will depose Henry. 158:Henry will depose the duke. 2235: 1601:Syntax–semantics interface 500: 433:Columbia Journalism Review 33: 26: 2093:Question under discussion 2043:Conversational scoreboard 1820:Intersective modification 1805:Homogeneity (linguistics) 1142:10.1016/j.jml.2004.11.003 1003:Mayes, Ian (2000-04-13). 708:Eats, Shoots & Leaves 638:Differences in processing 471:In humour and advertising 2153:Distributional semantics 783:Oaks, Dallin D. (2010). 761:Transderivational search 629:The good-enough approach 625:understanding language. 102:syntactic disambiguation 2148:Computational semantics 1885:Subsective modification 1689:Propositional attitudes 1280:10.1111/1467-8721.00158 956:, Perigee Books, 1987. 936:, Dolphin Books, 1980, 917:New York Times Magazine 756:The Purple People Eater 670:reduced relative clause 584:Unrestricted race model 540:Competition-based model 414:. A common form is the 340:The Purple People Eater 319:Lesbian Vampire Killers 132:"garden path" sentences 2178:Philosophy of language 1815:Inalienable possession 1795:Free choice inferences 1790:Faultless disagreement 1561:Generalized quantifier 1220:Memory & Cognition 1193:10.1006/jmla.1998.2600 387: 179: 2073:Plural quantification 1967:Inquisitive semantics 1932:Alternative semantics 501:Further information: 410:, creating syntactic 18:Syntactical ambiguity 2058:Function application 1865:Responsive predicate 1855:Privative adjectives 1406:Cognitive Psychology 932:Gloria Cooper, ed., 885:(King James Version) 719:Garden path sentence 682:garden path sentence 205:Edward II of England 88:frivolous litigation 49:structural ambiguity 2143:Cognitive semantics 2108:Strawson entailment 2053:Existential closure 1997:Situation semantics 1900:Temperature paradox 1870:Rising declaratives 1835:Modal subordination 1810:Hurford disjunction 1770:Discourse relations 1360:2013PLoSO...854141J 1233:10.3758/MC.36.1.201 920:, January 27, 2010 902:, February 19, 2001 643:Children and adults 192:Christopher Marlowe 154:William Shakespeare 45:Syntactic ambiguity 2188:Semantics of logic 2113:Strict conditional 2083:Quantifier raising 2048:Downward entailing 2028:Autonomy of syntax 1957:Generative grammar 1937:Categorial grammar 1875:Scalar implicature 1780:Epistemic modality 1755:De dicto and de re 842:2016-08-03 at the 547:globally ambiguous 509:semantic ambiguity 197:Isabella of France 113:Globally ambiguous 29:protein structures 2196: 2195: 2168:Logic translation 2131: 2130: 2123:Universal grinder 2103:Squiggle operator 2063:Meaning postulate 2002:Supervaluationism 1972:Intensional logic 1952:Dynamic semantics 1913: 1912: 1745:Crossover effects 1694:Tense–aspect–mood 1674:Lexical semantics 1080:978-3-642-32612-7 869:978-94-007-1463-2 746:Reading span task 702:Dangling modifier 697:Ambiguous grammar 656:memory can hold. 479:in the 1930 film 400:telegraphic style 398:are written in a 122:Locally ambiguous 16:(Redirected from 2226: 2173:Linguistics wars 2098:Semantic parsing 1987:Montague grammar 1922: 1765:Deontic modality 1619: 1606:Truth conditions 1541:Compositionality 1534:Central concepts 1520: 1513: 1506: 1497: 1473: 1472: 1444: 1438: 1437: 1401: 1392: 1391: 1381: 1371: 1339: 1333: 1332: 1330: 1328: 1322: 1316:. Archived from 1315: 1306: 1300: 1299: 1263: 1254: 1253: 1235: 1211: 1205: 1204: 1176: 1170: 1169: 1168: 1152: 1146: 1145: 1135: 1115: 1100: 1091: 1085: 1084: 1064: 1058: 1051: 1045: 1042: 1036: 1026: 1020: 1019: 1017: 1016: 1000: 994: 984: 978: 977: 970: 964: 950: 944: 930: 924: 909: 903: 892: 886: 880: 874: 873: 853: 847: 833: 827: 820: 814: 807: 801: 800: 780: 672:compared to the 554:Reanalysis model 465:Second World War 408:omits the copula 385: 182: 47:, also known as 21: 2234: 2233: 2229: 2228: 2227: 2225: 2224: 2223: 2199: 2198: 2197: 2192: 2127: 2016: 1977:Lambda calculus 1909: 1880:Sloppy identity 1840:Opaque contexts 1775:Donkey anaphora 1740:Counterfactuals 1708: 1610: 1529: 1524: 1482: 1477: 1476: 1446: 1445: 1441: 1403: 1402: 1395: 1341: 1340: 1336: 1326: 1324: 1323:on 10 June 2015 1320: 1313: 1308: 1307: 1303: 1265: 1264: 1257: 1213: 1212: 1208: 1178: 1177: 1173: 1166:10.1.1.165.9576 1154: 1153: 1149: 1133:10.1.1.165.8161 1117: 1116: 1103: 1092: 1088: 1081: 1066: 1065: 1061: 1052: 1048: 1043: 1039: 1027: 1023: 1014: 1012: 1002: 1001: 997: 985: 981: 972: 971: 967: 952:Gloria Cooper, 951: 947: 931: 927: 910: 906: 893: 889: 881: 877: 870: 855: 854: 850: 844:Wayback Machine 834: 830: 821: 817: 808: 804: 797: 782: 781: 774: 769: 693: 674:relative clause 662: 645: 640: 631: 586: 556: 542: 537: 525: 505: 499: 482:Animal Crackers 473: 418:type. The name 392: 386: 383: 140: 124: 115: 110: 108:Different forms 42: 39: 32: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 2232: 2230: 2222: 2221: 2216: 2211: 2201: 2200: 2194: 2193: 2191: 2190: 2185: 2180: 2175: 2170: 2165: 2163:Inferentialism 2160: 2158:Formal grammar 2155: 2150: 2145: 2139: 2137: 2133: 2132: 2129: 2128: 2126: 2125: 2120: 2115: 2110: 2105: 2100: 2095: 2090: 2085: 2080: 2078:Possible world 2075: 2070: 2065: 2060: 2055: 2050: 2045: 2040: 2035: 2030: 2024: 2022: 2018: 2017: 2015: 2014: 2009: 2004: 1999: 1994: 1989: 1984: 1979: 1974: 1969: 1964: 1962:Glue semantics 1959: 1954: 1949: 1944: 1939: 1934: 1928: 1926: 1925:Formal systems 1919: 1915: 1914: 1911: 1910: 1908: 1907: 1902: 1897: 1892: 1887: 1882: 1877: 1872: 1867: 1862: 1857: 1852: 1850:Polarity items 1847: 1842: 1837: 1832: 1827: 1822: 1817: 1812: 1807: 1802: 1797: 1792: 1787: 1782: 1777: 1772: 1767: 1762: 1757: 1752: 1747: 1742: 1737: 1735:Conservativity 1732: 1727: 1722: 1716: 1714: 1710: 1709: 1707: 1706: 1701: 1699:Quantification 1696: 1691: 1686: 1681: 1676: 1671: 1666: 1661: 1656: 1651: 1646: 1641: 1636: 1631: 1625: 1623: 1616: 1612: 1611: 1609: 1608: 1603: 1598: 1593: 1588: 1583: 1578: 1576:Presupposition 1573: 1568: 1563: 1558: 1553: 1548: 1543: 1537: 1535: 1531: 1530: 1525: 1523: 1522: 1515: 1508: 1500: 1494: 1493: 1488: 1481: 1480:External links 1478: 1475: 1474: 1455:(3): 348–368. 1439: 1393: 1334: 1301: 1255: 1226:(1): 201–216. 1206: 1187:(4): 558–592. 1171: 1147: 1126:(2): 284–307. 1101: 1086: 1079: 1059: 1046: 1037: 1021: 995: 987:1997 Headlines 979: 974:"Language Log" 965: 945: 925: 904: 887: 875: 868: 848: 828: 815: 802: 795: 771: 770: 768: 765: 764: 763: 758: 753: 748: 743: 741:Paraprosdokian 738: 733: 728: 721: 716: 711: 704: 699: 692: 689: 661: 658: 653:working memory 644: 641: 639: 636: 630: 627: 618: 617: 614: 611: 585: 582: 577: 576: 573: 570: 555: 552: 541: 538: 536: 533: 524: 521: 498: 495: 472: 469: 420:crash blossoms 406:) which often 391: 388: 381: 370: 369: 368: 367: 364: 355: 354: 353: 352: 349: 335: 334: 333: 332: 329: 326: 314: 313: 312: 311: 308: 305: 302: 299: 290: 289: 288: 287: 284: 281: 278: 275: 266: 265: 264: 263: 255: 254: 251: 248: 245: 223: 222: 221: 220: 217: 213: 212: 174: 173: 172: 171: 163: 162: 159: 139: 136: 123: 120: 114: 111: 109: 106: 40: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 2231: 2220: 2217: 2215: 2212: 2210: 2207: 2206: 2204: 2189: 2186: 2184: 2181: 2179: 2176: 2174: 2171: 2169: 2166: 2164: 2161: 2159: 2156: 2154: 2151: 2149: 2146: 2144: 2141: 2140: 2138: 2134: 2124: 2121: 2119: 2116: 2114: 2111: 2109: 2106: 2104: 2101: 2099: 2096: 2094: 2091: 2089: 2086: 2084: 2081: 2079: 2076: 2074: 2071: 2069: 2066: 2064: 2061: 2059: 2056: 2054: 2051: 2049: 2046: 2044: 2041: 2039: 2036: 2034: 2031: 2029: 2026: 2025: 2023: 2019: 2013: 2010: 2008: 2005: 2003: 2000: 1998: 1995: 1993: 1990: 1988: 1985: 1983: 1980: 1978: 1975: 1973: 1970: 1968: 1965: 1963: 1960: 1958: 1955: 1953: 1950: 1948: 1945: 1943: 1940: 1938: 1935: 1933: 1930: 1929: 1927: 1923: 1920: 1916: 1906: 1903: 1901: 1898: 1896: 1893: 1891: 1888: 1886: 1883: 1881: 1878: 1876: 1873: 1871: 1868: 1866: 1863: 1861: 1858: 1856: 1853: 1851: 1848: 1846: 1845:Performatives 1843: 1841: 1838: 1836: 1833: 1831: 1828: 1826: 1825:Logophoricity 1823: 1821: 1818: 1816: 1813: 1811: 1808: 1806: 1803: 1801: 1798: 1796: 1793: 1791: 1788: 1786: 1783: 1781: 1778: 1776: 1773: 1771: 1768: 1766: 1763: 1761: 1758: 1756: 1753: 1751: 1748: 1746: 1743: 1741: 1738: 1736: 1733: 1731: 1728: 1726: 1723: 1721: 1718: 1717: 1715: 1711: 1705: 1702: 1700: 1697: 1695: 1692: 1690: 1687: 1685: 1682: 1680: 1677: 1675: 1672: 1670: 1667: 1665: 1662: 1660: 1659:Evidentiality 1657: 1655: 1652: 1650: 1647: 1645: 1642: 1640: 1637: 1635: 1632: 1630: 1627: 1626: 1624: 1620: 1617: 1613: 1607: 1604: 1602: 1599: 1597: 1594: 1592: 1589: 1587: 1584: 1582: 1579: 1577: 1574: 1572: 1569: 1567: 1564: 1562: 1559: 1557: 1554: 1552: 1549: 1547: 1544: 1542: 1539: 1538: 1536: 1532: 1528: 1521: 1516: 1514: 1509: 1507: 1502: 1501: 1498: 1492: 1489: 1487: 1484: 1483: 1479: 1470: 1466: 1462: 1458: 1454: 1450: 1443: 1440: 1435: 1431: 1427: 1423: 1419: 1415: 1411: 1407: 1400: 1398: 1394: 1389: 1385: 1380: 1375: 1370: 1365: 1361: 1357: 1354:(1): e54141. 1353: 1349: 1345: 1338: 1335: 1319: 1312: 1305: 1302: 1297: 1293: 1289: 1285: 1281: 1277: 1273: 1269: 1262: 1260: 1256: 1251: 1247: 1243: 1239: 1234: 1229: 1225: 1221: 1217: 1210: 1207: 1202: 1198: 1194: 1190: 1186: 1182: 1175: 1172: 1167: 1162: 1158: 1151: 1148: 1143: 1139: 1134: 1129: 1125: 1121: 1114: 1112: 1110: 1108: 1106: 1102: 1098: 1097: 1090: 1087: 1082: 1076: 1072: 1071: 1063: 1060: 1056: 1050: 1047: 1041: 1038: 1034: 1030: 1025: 1022: 1010: 1006: 999: 996: 992: 988: 983: 980: 975: 969: 966: 963: 962:0-399-51406-6 959: 955: 949: 946: 943: 942:0-385-15828-9 939: 935: 929: 926: 923: 919: 918: 913: 908: 905: 901: 897: 891: 888: 884: 883:Zechariah 1:7 879: 876: 871: 865: 861: 860: 852: 849: 845: 841: 838: 832: 829: 825: 819: 816: 812: 806: 803: 798: 796:9781441141378 792: 788: 787: 779: 777: 773: 766: 762: 759: 757: 754: 752: 749: 747: 744: 742: 739: 737: 734: 732: 729: 727: 726: 722: 720: 717: 715: 712: 710: 709: 705: 703: 700: 698: 695: 694: 690: 688: 686: 683: 679: 675: 671: 667: 659: 657: 654: 649: 642: 637: 635: 628: 626: 622: 615: 612: 609: 608: 607: 606: 602: 598: 595: 591: 583: 581: 574: 571: 568: 567: 566: 564: 560: 553: 551: 548: 539: 534: 532: 529: 528:Immanuel Kant 522: 520: 518: 514: 510: 504: 496: 494: 490: 488: 484: 483: 478: 470: 468: 466: 462: 458: 453: 451: 447: 443: 439: 435: 434: 429: 425: 421: 417: 413: 409: 405: 401: 397: 389: 380: 376: 374: 365: 362: 361: 360: 357: 356: 350: 347: 346: 345: 341: 337: 336: 330: 327: 324: 323: 321: 320: 316: 315: 309: 306: 303: 300: 297: 296: 295: 292: 291: 285: 282: 279: 276: 273: 272: 271: 268: 267: 261: 260:cross-dresser 257: 256: 252: 249: 246: 243: 242: 240: 236: 232: 228: 225: 224: 218: 215: 214: 210: 206: 202: 198: 195: 194: 193: 189: 188: 183: 181: 176: 175: 169: 165: 164: 160: 157: 156: 155: 152:(1.4.30), by 151: 150: 145: 142: 141: 137: 135: 133: 129: 128:disambiguated 121: 119: 112: 107: 105: 103: 99: 98: 93: 89: 85: 81: 80:jurisprudence 76: 74: 70: 66: 62: 58: 54: 50: 46: 37: 30: 19: 2118:Type shifter 2088:Quantization 2038:Continuation 1905:Veridicality 1785:Exhaustivity 1750:Cumulativity 1669:Indexicality 1649:Definiteness 1644:Conditionals 1571:Logical form 1452: 1448: 1442: 1412:(1): 56–98. 1409: 1405: 1351: 1347: 1337: 1325:. Retrieved 1318:the original 1304: 1274:(1): 11–15. 1271: 1267: 1223: 1219: 1209: 1184: 1180: 1174: 1156: 1150: 1123: 1119: 1094: 1089: 1073:. Springer. 1069: 1062: 1049: 1040: 1032: 1029:Fritz Spiegl 1024: 1013:. Retrieved 1008: 998: 982: 968: 953: 948: 933: 928: 915: 907: 899: 896:The Guardian 895: 890: 878: 858: 851: 831: 818: 805: 785: 751:Serial comma 723: 714:Equivocation 706: 684: 666:reading span 663: 646: 632: 623: 619: 604: 603: 599: 587: 578: 562: 561: 557: 543: 526: 517:logical form 506: 491: 481: 477:Groucho Marx 474: 454: 449: 446:Language Log 441: 437: 431: 419: 393: 390:In headlines 378: 371: 358: 317: 293: 269: 237:(written by 226: 185: 177: 147: 143: 125: 116: 101: 95: 92:parse forest 91: 77: 56: 52: 48: 44: 43: 2033:Context set 2007:Type theory 1890:Subtrigging 1654:Disjunction 1581:Proposition 922:online text 590:probability 461:World War I 416:garden path 344:Sheb Wooley 97:parse trees 57:amphibology 2203:Categories 2183:Pragmatics 1830:Mirativity 1596:Speech act 1551:Entailment 1546:Denotation 1327:4 November 1015:2009-06-05 991:Snopes.com 912:Ben Zimmer 894:headline, 767:References 685:because of 457:apocryphal 404:headlinese 394:Newspaper 239:Ray Davies 211:is placed. 73:word order 36:amphibians 2219:Semantics 2209:Ambiguity 1982:Mereology 1918:Formalism 1800:Givenness 1725:Cataphora 1713:Phenomena 1704:Vagueness 1634:Ambiguity 1586:Reference 1566:Intension 1556:Extension 1469:0749-596X 1288:0963-7214 1242:1532-5946 1201:0749-596X 1161:CiteSeerX 1128:CiteSeerX 428:JAL crash 424:headlines 412:ambiguity 396:headlines 373:Aristotle 235:the Kinks 187:Edward II 84:contracts 53:amphiboly 2136:See also 2021:Concepts 1895:Telicity 1730:Coercion 1684:Negation 1679:Modality 1629:Anaphora 1434:23695158 1388:23349807 1348:PLOS ONE 1250:18323075 1011:. London 1009:Guardian 900:Barron's 840:Archived 691:See also 664:For low 503:Polysemy 382:—  149:Henry VI 138:Examples 61:sentence 1639:Binding 1426:1537232 1379:3547875 1356:Bibcode 1296:4126375 523:Kantian 2214:Syntax 2068:Monads 1615:Topics 1467:  1432:  1424:  1386:  1376:  1294:  1286:  1248:  1240:  1199:  1163:  1130:  1099:(1878) 1077:  960:  940:  866:  793:  594:Gompel 535:Models 168:poetry 65:syntax 1760:De se 1664:Focus 1622:Areas 1591:Scope 1430:S2CID 1321:(PDF) 1314:(PDF) 1292:S2CID 440:and " 342:" by 233:" by 209:comma 55:, or 1465:ISSN 1422:PMID 1384:PMID 1329:2013 1284:ISSN 1246:PMID 1238:ISSN 1197:ISSN 1075:ISBN 958:ISBN 938:ISBN 864:ISBN 791:ISBN 231:Lola 199:and 2012:TTR 1457:doi 1414:doi 1374:PMC 1364:doi 1276:doi 1228:doi 1189:doi 1138:doi 989:at 489:". 452:". 229:— " 190:by 78:In 2205:: 1463:. 1453:25 1451:. 1428:. 1420:. 1410:24 1408:. 1396:^ 1382:. 1372:. 1362:. 1350:. 1346:. 1290:. 1282:. 1272:11 1270:. 1258:^ 1244:. 1236:. 1224:36 1222:. 1218:. 1195:. 1185:39 1183:. 1159:, 1136:. 1124:52 1122:. 1104:^ 1031:, 1007:. 775:^ 565:: 519:. 444:. 241:) 184:— 146:— 104:. 51:, 1519:e 1512:t 1505:v 1471:. 1459:: 1436:. 1416:: 1390:. 1366:: 1358:: 1352:8 1331:. 1298:. 1278:: 1252:. 1230:: 1203:. 1191:: 1144:. 1140:: 1083:. 1018:. 993:. 976:. 872:. 799:. 402:( 338:" 262:. 38:. 31:. 20:)

Index

Syntactical ambiguity
protein structures
amphibians
sentence
syntax
meanings of individual words
word order
jurisprudence
contracts
frivolous litigation
parse trees
disambiguated
"garden path" sentences
Henry VI
William Shakespeare
poetry
Edward II
Christopher Marlowe
Isabella of France
Roger Mortimer, 1st Earl of March
Edward II of England
comma
Lola
the Kinks
Ray Davies
cross-dresser
Lesbian Vampire Killers
The Purple People Eater
Sheb Wooley
Aristotle

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑