Knowledge (XXG)

Thick concept

Source 📝

119:
analyzed as a conjunction of a descriptive part and an evaluative part which, at least in principle, may be separated. A basic feature of this analysis is thus that the descriptive content of a thick concept may be given in absence of the evaluative content. Returning to the example of courage, ‘…is courageous’ could on this account be analyzed as something along the lines of ‘…opposing danger to promote a valued end’ and ‘this is (prima facie) good-making’. The evaluative part, on this view, may thus be characterized as a ‘prescriptive flag’ attached to the concept. It is, on this view, in principle possible to construct a completely descriptive concept – i.e. without evaluative force – that picked out the same features of the world.
123:
profoundly involved in the practice of using it; one cannot understand a thick concept without also understanding its evaluative point. Therefore, descriptive terms cannot completely fill in the ‘along the lines’ of a description such as ‘…opposing danger to promote a valued end’. These descriptions may allow the novice to see the salient features. However a hooking on to the evaluative perspective allows the person to fully understand the 'thick' concept.
110:. Moral realists have argued that the world-guided content and the action-guiding content cannot be usefully separated, indicating that competent use of thick concepts constitutes ethical knowledge. Expressivists, favoring an account of moral values as attitudes projected onto the world, wish to maintain a distinction between the (morally neutral) descriptive features of a thick concept and the evaluative attitudes that typically go with them. 59:. Courage for example, may be given a rough characterization in descriptive terms as '...opposing danger to promote a valued end'. At the same time, characterizing someone as courageous typically involves expressing a pro-attitude, or a (prima facie) good-making quality – i.e. an evaluative statement. 122:
This account of thick concepts has been criticized by other theorists, notably of moral realist persuasion. In their view, the only way to understand a thick concept is to understand the descriptive and evaluative aspects as a whole. The idea is that, for a thick concept, the evaluative aspect is
118:
Thick concepts seem to combine the descriptive features of natural concepts such as water with an evaluative content similar to the thin evaluative concepts such as good and right. How are we to understand this ‘combination’? Many theorists treat it as a conjunctive: a thick concept should be
215:
The rationale for calling an action 'cruel' rather than merely describing it in more neutral terms is to tune into this evaluative aspect. Cf. McDowell 1981.
67:
Thick concepts thus seem to occupy a 'middle position' between (thin) descriptive concepts and (thin) evaluative concepts. Descriptive concepts such as
349: 35:) is a kind of concept that both has a significant degree of descriptive content and is evaluatively loaded. Paradigmatic examples are various 330: 91:
are commonly believed to pick out features of the world rather than provide reasons for action, whereas evaluative concepts such as
367: 99:
are commonly believed to provide reasons for action rather than picking out genuine features of the world.
206:
McDowell 1978, 1979, 1981; Williams 1985; Dancy 1995, 2004; McNaughton and Rawling 2000; and Little 2000.
142: 137: 304:
McNaughton, D. and Rawling, P. (2000) Unprincipled Ethics, in Hooker and Little 2000, 256–275.
340: 301:, eds. S. Holtzman and C. Leich, London & Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 141–162. 344: 245:
Dancy, J. (1995) In Defence of Thick Concepts, in French, Uehling, and Wettstein eds.,
361: 103: 307: 107: 102:
This 'double feature' of thick concepts has made them the point of debate between
20: 132: 280:
Little, M. (2000) Moral Generalities Revisited, in Hooker and Little 2000.
239: 353:(Spring 2021 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 283:
McDowell, J. (1978) Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?
188:
Catherine Elgin calls this the “skeleton account” in Elgin 2005, 343.
81: 36: 325: 69: 87: 75: 40: 234:
Blomberg, O. (2007) Disentangling The Thick Concept Argument,
297:
McDowell, J. (1981), Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following, in
285:
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume
266:
Gibbard, A. (1992) Thick Concepts and Warrant For Feelings,
249:, Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. 16:
Concept with both descriptive and evaluative content
314:, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. 8: 161:McDowell 1978, 1979, 1981; Dancy 1995, 2004. 259:Elgin, C. (2005) Williams on Truthfulness, 290:McDowell, J. (1979), Virtue and Reason, 179:Hare 1952, Gibbard 1992, Blackburn 1998. 350:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 268:Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 154: 7: 331:Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 312:Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy 273:Hooker, B. and Little, M. (2000), 236:Sats: Nordic Journal of Philosophy 14: 247:Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20 299:Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule 114:Two accounts of thick concepts 1: 170:Gibbard 1992, Blackburn 1998. 277:, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 261:The Philosophical Quarterly 256:, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 231:, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 384: 254:Ethics without Principles 341:"Thick Ethical Concepts" 339:Väyrynen, Pekka (2021). 33:thick evaluative concept 29:thick normative concept 227:Blackburn, S. (1998) 270:66 (Supplementary). 275:Moral Particularism 143:Emotive conjugation 138:Meaning (semiotics) 108:moral expressivists 368:Concepts in ethics 197:Williams 1985, 141 252:Dancy, J. (2004) 63:A middle position 375: 354: 345:Zalta, Edward N. 335: 326:"Thick Concepts" 294:62(3), 331–350. 238:, 8(2), 63–78. ( 216: 213: 207: 204: 198: 195: 189: 186: 180: 177: 171: 168: 162: 159: 127:Related concepts 383: 382: 378: 377: 376: 374: 373: 372: 358: 357: 338: 324:Kyle, Brent G. 323: 320: 229:Ruling Passions 225: 220: 219: 214: 210: 205: 201: 196: 192: 187: 183: 178: 174: 169: 165: 160: 156: 151: 129: 116: 65: 17: 12: 11: 5: 381: 379: 371: 370: 360: 359: 356: 355: 336: 319: 318:External links 316: 224: 221: 218: 217: 208: 199: 190: 181: 172: 163: 153: 152: 150: 147: 146: 145: 140: 135: 128: 125: 115: 112: 104:moral realists 64: 61: 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 380: 369: 366: 365: 363: 352: 351: 346: 342: 337: 333: 332: 327: 322: 321: 317: 315: 313: 309: 305: 302: 300: 295: 293: 288: 286: 281: 278: 276: 271: 269: 264: 262: 257: 255: 250: 248: 243: 241: 237: 232: 230: 222: 212: 209: 203: 200: 194: 191: 185: 182: 176: 173: 167: 164: 158: 155: 148: 144: 141: 139: 136: 134: 131: 130: 126: 124: 120: 113: 111: 109: 105: 100: 98: 94: 90: 89: 84: 83: 78: 77: 72: 71: 62: 60: 58: 54: 50: 46: 42: 38: 34: 30: 26: 25:thick concept 22: 348: 329: 311: 308:Williams, B. 306: 303: 298: 296: 291: 289: 284: 282: 279: 274: 272: 267: 265: 260: 258: 253: 251: 246: 244: 235: 233: 228: 226: 223:Bibliography 211: 202: 193: 184: 175: 166: 157: 121: 117: 101: 96: 92: 86: 80: 74: 68: 66: 56: 53:truthfulness 52: 48: 44: 32: 28: 27:(sometimes: 24: 18: 287:52, 13–29. 149:References 21:philosophy 133:Relevance 362:Category 57:kindness 43:such as 347:(ed.). 310:(1985) 49:cruelty 45:courage 37:virtues 292:Monist 82:length 343:. In 93:right 70:water 41:vices 31:, or 263:55. 240:link 106:and 97:good 95:and 88:mass 85:and 76:gold 55:and 39:and 23:, a 19:In 364:: 328:. 242:) 79:, 73:, 51:, 47:, 334:.

Index

philosophy
virtues
vices
water
gold
length
mass
moral realists
moral expressivists
Relevance
Meaning (semiotics)
Emotive conjugation
link
Williams, B.
"Thick Concepts"
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
"Thick Ethical Concepts"
Zalta, Edward N.
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Category
Concepts in ethics

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑