Knowledge (XXG)

User:Peter Damian/logic

Source 📝

328:, where Aristotelean logic is unable to satisfactorily render such sentences as "Some guys have all the luck", because both quantities "all" and "some" may be relevant in an inference, but the fixed scheme that Aristotle used allows only one to govern the inference. Just as linguists recognise recursive structure in natural languages, it appears that logic needs recursive structure. 406:. . Thus truth and falsity are no more than the agreement or disagreement of ideas. This suggests obvious difficulties, leading Locke to distinguish between 'real' truth, when our ideas have 'real existence' and 'imaginary' or 'verbal' truth, where ideas like harpies or centaurs exist only in the mind (Essay IV. v. 1-8). This view ( 518:' was never fully integrated into the theory of the 'categorical syllogism'. This was partly because of the resistance to reducing the categorical judgment 'Every S is P' to the so-called hypothetical judgment 'if anything is S, it is P'. The first was thought to imply 'some S is P', the second was not, and as late as 1911 in the 161:), only the logical principles stated in schematic terms belong to logic, and not those given in concrete terms. The concrete terms 'man', 'mortal' &c are analogous to the substitution values of the schematic placeholders 'A', 'B', 'C', which were called the 'matter' (Greek 'hyle') of the inference. 596:
and others, was the 'Logic of the Pure Idea'. The central feature of this view is the identification of Logic and Metaphysics. The Universe has its origin in the categories of thought. Thought in its fullest development becomes the Absolute Idea, a divine mind evolving itself in the development of
511:(or 'mode of positing'). Its Latin formulation is 'Posito antecedente ponitur consequens'. The Latin formulations of many other rules such as 'ex falso quodlibet' (anything follows from a falsehood), 'reductio ad absurdum' (disproof by showing the consequence is absurd) also date from this period. 475:
was the first to define the truth conditions of such an implication: false only when the antecedent p is true and the consequent q is false, in all other cases true. An inference, on the other hand, consists of two separately asserted propositions of the form 'p therefore q'. An inference is not
544:
took this one step further. He begins with the assumption of the empiricist philosophers, that all knowledge whatsoever is internal to the mind, and that we have no genuine knowledge of 'things in themselves'. Furthermore, (an idea he seemed to have got from Hume) the material of knowledge is a
378:
presents a comprehensive account of the necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of simple sentences, in order to show which arguments are valid and which are not. Thus 'every A is B' is true if and only if there is something for which 'A' stands for, and there is nothing for which 'A'
172:
which is of the form 'is' or 'is not'; (3) a predicate (e.g. 'mortal'). Thus: all men are mortal. The logical constants such as 'all', 'no' and so on, plus sentential connectives such as 'and' and 'or' were called 'syncategorematic' terms (from the Greek 'kategorei' – to predicate, and 'syn' –
78:
1. Into the study of arguments capable of rigorous demonstration, to which the concept of 'validity' genuinely applies; and the study and exposition of the principles underlying arguments which are not necessarily demonstratively sound, but which are persuasive, or which are likely to give an
135:
of the argument. It is necessary because indicative sentences of ordinary language show a considerable variety of form and complexity. It requires, first, ignoring those grammatical features which are irrelevant to logic (such as gender, declension (if the argument is in Latin), replacing
143:
Second, certain parts of the sentence must be replaced with schematic letters. Thus, for example, the expression 'all A's are B's' shows the logical form which is common to the sentences 'all men are mortals', 'all cats are carnivores', 'all Greeks are philosophers' and so on.
573:
However, this seems to be an arbitrary arrangement, driven by the desire to present a harmonious appearance than from any underlying method or system. For example, the triple nature of each division forced him to add artificial categories such as the infinite judgment.
63:
There is no universal agreement as to the exact scope and subject matter of Logic, but it has traditionally included the classification of arguments, the systematic exposition of the 'logical form' common to all valid arguments, and the study of fallacies and paradoxes.
136:
conjunctions which are not relevant to logic (such as 'but') with logical conjunctions like 'and' and replacing ambiguous or alternative logical expressions ('any', 'every' &c) with expressions of a standard type (such as 'all', or the universal quantifier
55:
is one where there is a specific relation of logical support between the assumptions of the argument and its conclusion. (In ordinary discourse, the conclusion of such an argument may be signified by words like 'therefore', 'hence', 'ergo' and so on.) The
545:
succession of separate ideas which have no intrinsic connection and thus no real unity. In order that these disparate sensations be brought into some sort of order and coherence, there must be an internal mechanism in the mind which provides the
128:) of any valid argument type. The form of an argument is displayed by representing its sentences using the formal grammar and symbolism of a logical system in such a way as to display its similarity with all other arguments of the same type. 484:. This was given an apparently paradoxical formulation by Philo, who said that the implication 'if it is day, it is night' is true only at night, so the inference 'it is day, therefore it is night' is valid in the night, but not in the day. 183:
The modern view is more complex, since a single judgement of Aristotle's system will involve two or more logical connectives. For example, the sentence "All men are mortal" involves in term logic two non-logical terms "is a man" (here
507:. This is why many terms in logic are Latin. For example, the rule that licenses the move from the implication 'if p then q' plus the assertion of its antecedent p, to the assertion of the consequent q is known as 535:
In the periodic of scholastic philosophy, logic was predominantly Aristotelian. Following the decline of scholasticism, logic was thought of as an affair of ideas by early modern philosophers such as Locke and
311: 164:
The fundamental difference between modern formal logic and traditional or Aristotelian logic lies in their differing analysis of the logical form of the sentences they treat.
410:) was taken to the extreme in the nineteenth century, and is generally held by modern logicians to signify a low point in the decline of logic before the twentieth century. 394:, says that 'after conceiving things by our ideas, we compare these ideas, and, finding that some belong together and some do not, we unite or separate them. This is called 252: 223: 433:. The approach assumes that the meaning of the various parts of the propositions are given by the possible ways we can give a recursively specified group of 147:
That the concept of form is fundamental to logic was already recognized in ancient times. Aristotle uses variable letters to represent valid inferences the
476:
true or false, but valid or invalid. However, there is a connection between implication and inference, as follows: if the implication 'if p then q' is
522:
article on Logic, we find the Oxford logician T.H. Case arguing against Sigwart's and Brentano's modern analysis of the universal proposition. Cf.
168:
On the traditional view, the form of the sentence consists of (1) a subject (e.g. 'man') plus a sign of quantity ('all' or 'some' or 'no'); (2) the
180:, such as a quantifier with its bound variable, which are joined to by juxtaposition to other sentences, which in turn may have logical structure. 173:
together with. This is a fixed scheme, where each judgement has an identified quantity and copula, determining the logical form of the sentence.
386:
in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, these insights were lost. Early modern logic defined semantics purely as a relation between ideas.
413:
Modern semantics is in some ways closer to the medieval view, in rejecting such psychological truth-conditions. However, the introduction of
449:, and a mapping from propositions to the truth values "true" and "false". Model-theoretic semantics is one of the fundamental concepts of 157:
says that the introduction of variables was 'one of Aristotle's greatest inventions'). According to the followers of Aristotle (such as
581:
espoused in the nineteenth by Benno Erdmann and others. The view of historians of logic is that Kant's influence was negative.
421:, rendered impossible the kind of subject-predicate analysis that underlies medieval semantics. The main modern approach is 418: 325: 523: 347:
of the sentences that make it up, and so logic cannot completely avoid the need to provide some treatment of semantics.
97:
3. Deductive reasoning is divided into that which can be formalized by standard predicate logic (especially so-called
442: 257: 556:(in a somewhat different sense than employed by the Aristotelian logicians), of which he claims there are twelve: 362:, particularly in the thirteenth and fourteenth century, developed into a complex and sophisticated theory, called 176:
According to the modern view, the fundamental form of a simple sentence is given by a recursive schema, involving
366:. This showed how the truth of simple sentences, expressed schematically, depend on how the terms 'supposit' or 487:
The theory of inference (or 'consequences') was systematically developed in medieval times by logicians such as
430: 314: 589: 519: 434: 515: 472: 438: 585: 43:(but coming to mean thought or reasoning) is generally held to consist of the systematic study of the 60:
of an argument type is a schematic way of representing what is common to all arguments of that type.
102: 496: 469: 363: 338: 177: 91: 154: 593: 488: 375: 355: 98: 84: 17: 391: 359: 387: 228: 199: 193: 149: 414: 468:. An implication is a sentence of the form 'If p then q', and can be true or false. 541: 492: 426: 383: 578: 508: 450: 407: 371: 125: 94:
and deductive arguments. The present article deals with deductive arguments only.
324:
But equally, the modern view is more powerful: medieval logicians recognised the
318: 537: 446: 584:
Another view of logic espoused by Hegel and others of his school (such as
196:
the sentence involves the same two non-logical concepts, here analysed as
500: 158: 80: 351: 577:
This conception of logic eventually developed into an extreme form of
495:. It is uniquely medieval, though it has its origins in Aristotle's 169: 90:
2. Arguments capable of demonstration are further sub-divided into
101:) and that which apparently cannot. The latter is the province of 370:
certain extra-linguistic items. For example, in book II of his
514:
However, the theory of consequences, or of the so-called '
343:
The validity of an argument depends upon the meaning or
192:): the sentence is given by the judgement A(M,D). In 260: 231: 202: 79:
advantage against an opponent). The latter includes
445:is given by a mapping from terms to a universe of 305: 246: 217: 566:Relation (Categorical, Hypothetical, Disjunctive) 358:, gives a cursory outline of semantics which the 75:Logic has traditionally been divided as follows. 306:{\displaystyle \forall x.(m(x)\rightarrow d(x))} 379:stands for, which 'B' does not also stand for. 120:, in that it aims to analyse and represent the 569:Modality (Problematic, Assertoric, Apodictic) 108:4. Types of Predicate logic . Computation. 8: 87:, is taught in many American Universities. 560:Quantity (Singular, Particular, Universal) 549:by which we think, perceive and reason. 563:Quality (Affirmative, Negative, Infinite) 259: 230: 201: 313:, involving the logical connectives for 7: 480:, the inference 'p therefore q' is 261: 24: 83:. A further discipline known as 254:, and the sentence is given by 419:problem of multiple generality 326:problem of multiple generality 300: 297: 291: 285: 282: 276: 270: 241: 235: 212: 206: 1: 524:problem of existential import 437:from them to some predefined 131:This is known as showing the 31:Logic, from Classical Greek 505:De Syllogismis hypotheticis 464:is not to be confused with 443:first-order predicate logic 611: 531:Rival Conceptions of Logic 336: 423:model-theoretic semantics 435:interpretation functions 431:semantic theory of truth 315:universal quantification 188:) and "is mortal" (here 552:Kant calls these forms 520:Encyclopedia Britannica 441:: an interpretation of 516:hypothetical syllogism 417:, needed to solve the 382:During the decline of 307: 248: 219: 308: 249: 220: 153:. (For which reason 35:, originally meaning 439:mathematical domains 360:scholastic logicians 258: 247:{\displaystyle d(x)} 229: 218:{\displaystyle m(x)} 200: 178:logical connectives 103:philosophical logic 470:The Stoic logician 364:Supposition Theory 339:semantics of logic 303: 244: 215: 489:William of Ockham 402:, and in general 376:William of Ockham 356:On Interpretation 99:first-order logic 85:critical thinking 71:Division of Logic 18:User:Peter Damian 602: 392:Port Royal Logic 312: 310: 309: 304: 253: 251: 250: 245: 224: 222: 221: 216: 610: 609: 605: 604: 603: 601: 600: 599: 533: 473:Philo of Megara 459: 388:Antoine Arnauld 341: 335: 256: 255: 227: 226: 198: 197: 194:predicate logic 150:Prior Analytics 114: 73: 67: 29: 22: 21: 20: 12: 11: 5: 608: 606: 597:the Universe. 571: 570: 567: 564: 561: 532: 529: 458: 455: 415:quantification 337:Main article: 334: 331: 330: 329: 322: 302: 299: 296: 293: 290: 287: 284: 281: 278: 275: 272: 269: 266: 263: 243: 240: 237: 234: 214: 211: 208: 205: 181: 174: 113: 110: 72: 69: 53:valid argument 41:what is spoken 28: 25: 23: 15: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 607: 598: 595: 591: 587: 582: 580: 575: 568: 565: 562: 559: 558: 557: 555: 550: 548: 543: 542:Immanuel Kant 539: 530: 528: 526: 525: 521: 517: 512: 510: 506: 502: 498: 494: 493:Walter Burley 490: 485: 483: 479: 474: 471: 467: 463: 456: 454: 452: 448: 444: 440: 436: 432: 428: 427:Alfred Tarski 424: 420: 416: 411: 409: 405: 401: 397: 393: 389: 385: 384:scholasticism 380: 377: 373: 372:Summa Logicae 369: 365: 361: 357: 354:, especially 353: 348: 346: 340: 332: 327: 323: 320: 316: 294: 288: 279: 273: 267: 264: 238: 232: 209: 203: 195: 191: 187: 182: 179: 175: 171: 167: 166: 165: 162: 160: 156: 152: 151: 145: 141: 139: 134: 129: 127: 123: 119: 111: 109: 106: 104: 100: 95: 93: 88: 86: 82: 76: 70: 68: 65: 61: 59: 54: 51:arguments. A 50: 46: 42: 38: 34: 26: 19: 583: 579:psychologism 576: 572: 553: 551: 546: 534: 527: 513: 509:modus ponens 504: 486: 481: 477: 465: 461: 460: 451:model theory 422: 412: 408:psychologism 403: 399: 395: 381: 367: 350:Aristotle's 349: 344: 342: 189: 185: 163: 148: 146: 142: 137: 133:logical form 132: 130: 126:logical form 121: 117: 115: 112:Logical Form 107: 96: 89: 77: 74: 66: 62: 57: 52: 48: 44: 40: 36: 32: 30: 466:implication 447:individuals 425:, based on 319:implication 155:Ɓukasiewicz 554:Categories 594:Bosanquet 462:Inference 457:Inference 396:affirming 368:stand for 345:semantics 333:Semantics 286:→ 262:∀ 116:Logic is 92:inductive 501:Boethius 159:Ammonius 81:rhetoric 37:the word 590:Bradley 404:judging 400:denying 390:in the 352:Organon 497:Topics 170:copula 118:formal 586:Lotze 547:forms 538:Hume 482:valid 49:valid 33:logos 27:Logic 16:< 499:and 491:and 478:true 317:and 225:and 124:(or 122:form 58:form 45:form 540:. 429:'s 398:or 140:). 47:of 39:or 592:, 588:, 503:' 453:. 374:, 105:. 321:. 301:) 298:) 295:x 292:( 289:d 283:) 280:x 277:( 274:m 271:( 268:. 265:x 242:) 239:x 236:( 233:d 213:) 210:x 207:( 204:m 190:D 186:M 138:A

Index

User:Peter Damian
rhetoric
critical thinking
inductive
first-order logic
philosophical logic
logical form
Prior Analytics
Ɓukasiewicz
Ammonius
copula
logical connectives
predicate logic
universal quantification
implication
problem of multiple generality
semantics of logic
Organon
On Interpretation
scholastic logicians
Supposition Theory
Summa Logicae
William of Ockham
scholasticism
Antoine Arnauld
Port Royal Logic
psychologism
quantification
problem of multiple generality
Alfred Tarski

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑