Knowledge (XXG)

Counterexample

Source 📝

95:, or she can attempt to find a counterexample of the statement if she suspects it to be false. In the latter case, a counterexample would be a rectangle that is not a square, such as a rectangle with two sides of length 5 and two sides of length 7. However, despite having found rectangles that were not squares, all the rectangles she did find had four sides. She then makes the new conjecture "All rectangles have four sides". This is logically weaker than her original conjecture, since every square has four sides, but not every four-sided shape is a square. 103:. For example, suppose that after a while, the mathematician above settled on the new conjecture "All shapes that are rectangles and have four sides of equal length are squares". This conjecture has two parts to the hypothesis: the shape must be 'a rectangle' and must have 'four sides of equal length'. The mathematician then would like to know if she can remove either assumption, and still maintain the truth of her conjecture. This means that she needs to check the truth of the following two statements: 640: 144:" is the number 2, as it is a prime number but is not an odd number. Neither of the numbers 7 or 10 is a counterexample, as neither of them are enough to contradict the statement. In this example, 2 is in fact the only possible counterexample to the statement, even though that alone is enough to contradict the statement. In a similar manner, the statement "All 261:, counterexamples are usually used to argue that a certain philosophical position is wrong by showing that it does not apply in certain cases. Alternatively, the first philosopher can modify their claim so that the counterexample no longer applies; this is analogous to when a mathematician modifies a conjecture because of a counterexample. 292:
Callicles might challenge Socrates' counterexample, arguing perhaps that the common rabble really are better than the nobles, or that even in their large numbers, they still are not stronger. But if Callicles accepts the counterexample, then he must either withdraw his claim, or modify it so that the
55:
In mathematics, counterexamples are often used to prove the boundaries of possible theorems. By using counterexamples to show that certain conjectures are false, mathematical researchers can then avoid going down blind alleys and learn to modify conjectures to produce provable theorems. It is
98:
The above example explained — in a simplified way — how a mathematician might weaken her conjecture in the face of counterexamples, but counterexamples can also be used to demonstrate the necessity of certain assumptions and
293:
counterexample no longer applies. For example, he might modify his claim to refer only to individual persons, requiring him to think of the common people as a collection of individuals rather than as a mob.
289:
of worse character. Thus Socrates has proposed a counterexample to Callicles' claim, by looking in an area that Callicles perhaps did not expect — groups of people rather than individual persons.
43:. For example, the fact that "student John Smith is not lazy" is a counterexample to the generalization "students are lazy", and both a counterexample to, and disproof of, the 554: 285:
replies that, because of their strength of numbers, the class of common rabble is stronger than the propertied class of nobles, even though the masses are
296:
As it happens, he modifies his claim to say "wiser" instead of "stronger", arguing that no amount of numerical superiority can make people wiser.
522: 670: 463: 159: 660: 625: 610: 593: 578: 563: 546: 412: 278:, trying to define what it means to say that some people are "better" than others, claims that those who are stronger are better. 188: 238: 601: 505: 310: 644: 510: 56:
sometimes said that mathematical development consists primarily in finding (and proving) theorems and counterexamples.
537: 127: 207: 675: 44: 532: 496: 315: 131: 242: 141: 234: 92: 387: 270: 230: 88: 621: 606: 589: 574: 559: 542: 528: 518: 501: 437: 81: 114:
A counterexample to (1) was already given above, and a counterexample to (2) is a non-square
427: 246: 215: 153: 223: 665: 200: 192: 145: 24: 654: 305: 219: 196: 432: 118:. Thus, the mathematician now knows that each assumption by itself is insufficient. 491: 363: 149: 137: 588:. Corrected reprint of the second (1965) edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY 338: 286: 36: 258: 173:
power. This conjecture was disproved in 1966, with a counterexample involving
100: 84:", and she is interested in knowing whether this statement is true or false. 77: 73: 40: 441: 156:" has the number 1 as a counterexample, as 1 is neither prime nor composite. 639: 275: 282: 65: 115: 265: 69: 32: 28: 211: 181: = 5 counterexamples are now known, as well as some 110:"All shapes that have four sides of equal length are squares". 413:"Counterexample to Euler's conjecture on sums of like powers" 162:
was disproved by counterexample. It asserted that at least
72:, and she wishes to prove certain theorems about them. She 31:
a counterexample disproves the generalization, and does so
571:Counterexamples in Probability and Real Analysis 616:Michael Copobianco & John Mulluzzo (1978) 584:Bernard R. Gelbaum, John M. H. Olmsted (2003) 555:Counterexamples in Probability and Statistics 552:Joseph P. Romano and Andrew F. Siegel (1986) 420:Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 107:"All shapes that are rectangles are squares." 8: 618:Examples and Counterexamples in Graph Theory 229:Other examples include the disproofs of the 203:imply optimal control laws that are linear. 426:(6). Americal Mathematical Society: 1079. 199:and a linear equation of evolution of the 431: 64:Suppose that a mathematician is studying 169:powers were necessary to sum to another 87:In this case, she can either attempt to 327: 136:A counterexample to the statement "all 191:shows that it is not always true (for 569:Gary L. Wise and Eric B. Hall (1993) 558:Chapman & Hall, New York, London 515:Proof in Mathematics: An Introduction 218:is false as shown by counterexamples 7: 573:. Oxford University Press, New York 333: 331: 16:Exception to a proposed general rule 605:Second edition, Wiley, Chichester 500:(1976) Cambridge University Press 14: 91:the truth of the statement using 638: 185: = 4 counterexamples. 160:Euler's sum of powers conjecture 433:10.1090/s0002-9904-1966-11654-3 602:Counterexamples in Probability 311:Exception that proves the rule 1: 462:Elkies, Noam (October 1988). 189:Witsenhausen's counterexample 239:Hilbert's fourteenth problem 671:Interpretation (philosophy) 586:Counterexamples in Analysis 538:Counterexamples in Topology 339:"Mathwords: Counterexample" 210:are mappings that preserve 128:Counterexamples in topology 122:Other mathematical examples 692: 599:Jordan M. Stoyanov (1997) 471:Mathematics of Computation 208:Euclidean plane isometries 125: 620:, Elsevier North-Holland 388:"What Is Counterexample?" 47:"all students are lazy." 661:Mathematical terminology 513:and Albert Daoud (2011) 45:universal quantification 411:Lander, Parkin (1966). 643:Quotations related to 533:J. Arthur Seebach, Jr. 497:Proofs and Refutations 464:"On A4 + B4 + C4 = D4" 316:Minimal counterexample 177: = 5; other 132:Minimal counterexample 23:is any exception to a 541:, Springer, New York 368:mathworld.wolfram.com 392:www.cut-the-knot.org 237:, the conjecture of 362:Weisstein, Eric W. 195:) that a quadratic 93:deductive reasoning 231:Seifert conjecture 529:Lynn Arthur Steen 523:978-0-646-54509-7 343:www.mathwords.com 243:Tait's conjecture 60:Rectangle example 35:in the fields of 683: 676:Methods of proof 642: 479: 478: 468: 459: 453: 452: 450: 448: 435: 417: 408: 402: 401: 399: 398: 384: 378: 377: 375: 374: 364:"Counterexample" 359: 353: 352: 350: 349: 335: 264:For example, in 247:Ganea conjecture 235:Pólya conjecture 193:control problems 691: 690: 686: 685: 684: 682: 681: 680: 651: 650: 635: 488: 486:Further reading 483: 482: 477:(184): 825–835. 466: 461: 460: 456: 446: 444: 415: 410: 409: 405: 396: 394: 386: 385: 381: 372: 370: 361: 360: 356: 347: 345: 337: 336: 329: 324: 302: 255: 224:squeeze mapping 146:natural numbers 134: 124: 62: 53: 17: 12: 11: 5: 689: 687: 679: 678: 673: 668: 663: 653: 652: 649: 648: 645:Counterexample 634: 633:External links 631: 630: 629: 614: 597: 582: 567: 550: 526: 517:, Kew, Sydney 511:James Franklin 508: 487: 484: 481: 480: 454: 403: 379: 354: 326: 325: 323: 320: 319: 318: 313: 308: 301: 298: 254: 251: 201:state variable 123: 120: 112: 111: 108: 61: 58: 52: 51:In mathematics 49: 25:generalization 21:counterexample 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 688: 677: 674: 672: 669: 667: 664: 662: 659: 658: 656: 646: 641: 637: 636: 632: 627: 626:0-444-00255-3 623: 619: 615: 612: 611:0-471-96538-3 608: 604: 603: 598: 595: 594:0-486-42875-3 591: 587: 583: 580: 579:0-19-507068-2 576: 572: 568: 565: 564:0-412-98901-8 561: 557: 556: 551: 548: 547:0-486-68735-X 544: 540: 539: 534: 530: 527: 524: 520: 516: 512: 509: 507: 503: 499: 498: 493: 490: 489: 485: 476: 472: 465: 458: 455: 443: 439: 434: 429: 425: 421: 414: 407: 404: 393: 389: 383: 380: 369: 365: 358: 355: 344: 340: 334: 332: 328: 321: 317: 314: 312: 309: 307: 306:Contradiction 304: 303: 299: 297: 294: 290: 288: 284: 279: 277: 273: 272: 267: 262: 260: 253:In philosophy 252: 250: 248: 244: 240: 236: 232: 227: 225: 221: 220:shear mapping 217: 213: 209: 204: 202: 198: 197:loss function 194: 190: 186: 184: 180: 176: 172: 168: 165: 161: 157: 155: 151: 147: 143: 139: 138:prime numbers 133: 129: 121: 119: 117: 109: 106: 105: 104: 102: 96: 94: 90: 85: 83: 79: 75: 71: 67: 59: 57: 50: 48: 46: 42: 38: 34: 30: 26: 22: 647:at Wikiquote 617: 600: 585: 570: 553: 536: 514: 495: 492:Imre Lakatos 474: 470: 457: 445:. Retrieved 423: 419: 406: 395:. Retrieved 391: 382: 371:. Retrieved 367: 357: 346:. Retrieved 342: 295: 291: 280: 269: 263: 256: 228: 205: 187: 182: 178: 174: 170: 166: 163: 158: 135: 113: 97: 86: 63: 54: 20: 18: 287:prima facie 148:are either 142:odd numbers 74:conjectures 37:mathematics 655:Categories 506:0521290384 397:2019-11-28 373:2019-11-28 348:2019-11-28 322:References 259:philosophy 245:, and the 214:, but the 126:See also: 101:hypothesis 78:rectangles 76:that "All 41:philosophy 33:rigorously 442:0273-0979 276:Callicles 154:composite 525:, ch. 6. 447:2 August 300:See also 283:Socrates 216:converse 66:geometry 535:(1978) 271:Gorgias 116:rhombus 82:squares 624:  609:  592:  577:  562:  545:  521:  504:  440:  233:, the 70:shapes 27:. In 666:Logic 467:(PDF) 416:(PDF) 266:Plato 150:prime 89:prove 29:logic 622:ISBN 607:ISBN 590:ISBN 575:ISBN 560:ISBN 543:ISBN 531:and 519:ISBN 502:ISBN 449:2018 438:ISSN 281:But 222:and 212:area 206:All 140:are 130:and 80:are 68:and 39:and 428:doi 268:'s 257:In 152:or 657:: 494:, 475:51 473:. 469:. 436:. 424:72 422:. 418:. 390:. 366:. 341:. 330:^ 274:, 249:. 241:, 226:. 19:A 628:. 613:. 596:. 581:. 566:. 549:. 451:. 430:: 400:. 376:. 351:. 183:n 179:n 175:n 171:n 167:n 164:n

Index

generalization
logic
rigorously
mathematics
philosophy
universal quantification
geometry
shapes
conjectures
rectangles
squares
prove
deductive reasoning
hypothesis
rhombus
Counterexamples in topology
Minimal counterexample
prime numbers
odd numbers
natural numbers
prime
composite
Euler's sum of powers conjecture
Witsenhausen's counterexample
control problems
loss function
state variable
Euclidean plane isometries
area
converse

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.