Knowledge

Models as Mediators

Source 📝

214:
the use of models as instruments for the exploration and development of theory and or for the design of better experiments. The third is their use to 'represent' beyond what a theory alone can offer. The fourth function is the capacity of the model to enhance learning - though this function is also present in the preceding three steps. Morrison and Morgan emphasize that models can thus be regarded as 'technologies for investigation' — one learns by manipulating and playing with them. Models
209:
We believe there is a significant connection between the autonomy of models and their ability to function as instruments. It is precisely because models are partially independent of both theories and the world that they have this autonomous component and so can be used as instrument of exploration in
205:
discusses the syntactic versus semantic view of theories and how these consider models. The second chapter by the same authors entitled 'Models as mediating instruments' — a key chapter in the economy of the volume, introduces the unifying theme of the work: the concept of models as mediators between
213:
The chapter also details what has been called a 'functionalist' articulation of the difference between models and theory, namely in four functions served by models: the first is how they are constructed deriving elements from one or more theories, other models, and the world. The second function is
311:
The 'functionalist' — rather than philosophical approach of the work, i.e. more about what a model does than what a model is, leaves several questions unanswered (or answered in different ways in different chapters). Furthermore, the examples are quite technical and detailed, not easy to read for
286:
Even the most simple-looking figure, i.e. absolute numbers, reflect an institutional structure, embody work of people (filling questionnaires) as consequence of which the actual figures represent a specific group of unemployed, namely those who found their job via the official employment offices.
220:
Chapter 3 by Margaret Morrison, entitled 'Models as autonomous agents', elaborates on the autonomy of models with example from physics. Chapter 4 'Built in justification' is from Marcel Boumans. Using examples from economics Boumans shows that models 'integrate a broader range of ingredients than
312:
the non initiated. Important epistemological questions left open concerns for example why individual models are constructed with the particular degrees of independence from theory and experiment. Being focused on models in physics, chemistry and economics, the book leaves out biological models.
294:
empirical adequacy and logical consistency are not the only criteria of models acceptance. The story told by a model matters to its acceptability, and thus to its function and quality. The argument is developed in the final chapter of the volume entitled 'Models and stories in hadron physics'.
303:
One review notes that while the title appears to promise a unified theory of models the chapters point instead to a universe of possible ways to characterize the nature and use of models. Acting as mediators, models are partly independent from both theory and world, and this independence, that
278:
Adrienne van den Boogard notes that 'the model is also a social and political device', and shows how institutions can be 'influenced (but were also conditioned by) the usage of different models and statistical techniques.' van den Boogard provides an illustration based on economic models and
142:. The book illustrate the concept of models as mediating between theory and the world and yet independent from both. It offers a historical and philosophical discussion of what models are and of what models do, with detailed examples written by the same editors and scholars such as 179:, to a new conception of theory as framed in therms of semantics, whereby models acquire a new prominence as 'fundamental unit of scientific theorizing, theories themselves being families of models'. Most of the examples in the book are quite articulated and pertinent to either 27: 307:
But the individual chapters make clear why Models as Mediators cannot possibly offer such a theory: the models dealt with in the book are so diverse and disparate that they cannot really be covered by a general description.
315:
The book lays the basis for a research programme for studying models from the point of view of scientific practice providing 'a potential bridge between philosophical theorising and the more practice-oriented approach of
206:
theory and world. Models may represent 'some aspect of our theories about the world'.{rp|11}. While they may act as mediators between theory and world, they are situated outside the theory-world axis'.{rp|11}
170:
Models and theories are related, so that an evolution in the perception of what a scientific theory is also chances the perception of what models are. The concept of scientific theory has moved from the
425:
Guala, F., Psillos, S. (October 2001). "Models as Mediators. Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, Mary S. Morgan and Margaret Morrison (eds.). Cambridge University Press, 1999, xi + 401 pages".
240:
discusses how an essential feature of models as mediators is to possibly replace the phenomenon itself in becoming the focus of scientific research, and illustrate this feature with an example from
224:
Chapter 5 from R.I.G. Hughes, discusses how the development of computers and simulation changed the relation between models and theory. It was the use of computer simulation that permitted the
271:
models, especially in fields such as quantum mechanics, quantum electrodynamics, classical mechanics and classical electromagnetic theory. For example, an abstract concept such as
606: 221:
only theory and data': these are theoretical notions, mathematical concepts and techniques, stylized facts, empirical data, policy views, analogies, metaphors.
267:
that are accurate to the phenomena from more theory-internal models, models that bridge element of the theory with one another, and that are named
611: 384: 304:
ensures the versatility of 'models as autonomous agents', is also the reason why they resist an attempt to a unified 'theory of models'.
105: 596: 601: 317: 263:'Models and the limit of theory: quantum Hamiltonians and the BCS model of superconductivity' distinguishes what she call 251:, 'Knife edge caricature modelling: the case of Marx's reproduction schema' is a 'detailed historical reconstruction' or 329: 57: 123: 75: 546: 500:
McCoy, C. D., Massimi, M. (1 January 2018). "Simplified models: a different perspective on models as mediators".
172: 236:
in 1813 are presented as 'paper tools' permitting representation and the construction of models. In Chapter 6
522: 175:' - whereby a theory can be seen as an axiomatic system to be dealt with in the context of the discipline of 217:
have the quality of a technology — the power of the model only becomes apparent in the context of its use.
61: 233: 548:
Models as epistemic artefacts: Toward a non-representationalist account of scientific representation
188: 527: 482: 442: 380: 256: 241: 134:
The volume looks at the working of models in the social and natural sciences, with a focus in
100: 517: 509: 474: 434: 291: 260: 159: 155: 237: 147: 202: 119: 37: 590: 565: 280: 248: 229: 191: 151: 143: 26: 283:
developed in the Netherlands. In discussing for example unemployment statistics:
225: 478: 513: 438: 531: 486: 446: 195: 184: 135: 65: 334:
Frigg, R. and Hartman, S., Models in Science, Stanford Encyclopedia, 2006.
252: 465:
Petersen, A. C. (1 October 2000). "Models as Technological Artefacts".
180: 139: 176: 20:
Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science
377:
Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science
115:
Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science
259:, with little general theory of models. Chapter 9 from 375:
Morgan, M. S., Morrison, M., eds. (28 November 1999).
99: 91: 81: 71: 53: 45: 33: 275:'can only exist in particular mechanical models'. 201:The introduction written by Margaret Morrison and 523:20.500.11820/ee6c3398-2777-40d9-bc89-a5d1d9c927cf 122:and Margaret Morrison and published in 1999 by 8: 564:Frigg, R., Hartmann, S. (27 February 2006). 19: 502:European Journal for Philosophy of Science 460: 458: 456: 433:(2). Cambridge University Press: 275–294. 420: 418: 416: 25: 18: 521: 414: 412: 410: 408: 406: 404: 402: 400: 398: 396: 370: 368: 344: 366: 364: 362: 360: 358: 356: 354: 352: 350: 348: 607:History of probability and statistics 473:(5). SAGE Publications Ltd: 793–799. 7: 570:Stanford Enciclopedia of Philosophy 232:chemical formulae as developed by 14: 146:, Marcel Boumans, R.I.G. Hughes, 118:is a multi-author book edited by 228:to be accepted. In Chapter 6 by 158:, Adrienne van den Boogard and 612:Science and technology studies 379:. Cambridge University Press. 1: 330:Sociology of quantification 58:Sociology of quantification 628: 479:10.1177/030631200030005006 427:Economics & Philosophy 124:Cambridge University Press 76:Cambridge University Press 514:10.1007/s13194-017-0178-0 467:Social Studies of Science 439:10.1017/S0266267101230272 24: 187:, with one, offered by 597:1999 non-fiction books 545:Knuuttila, T. (2005), 602:Philosophy of science 265:representative models 62:Philosophy of Science 234:Jöns Jacob Berzelius 189:historian of science 566:"Models in Science" 21: 386:978-0-521-65097-7 257:Marxian economics 242:superconductivity 111: 110: 41:Margaret Morrison 619: 581: 580: 578: 576: 561: 555: 554: 553: 542: 536: 535: 525: 497: 491: 490: 462: 451: 450: 422: 391: 390: 372: 292:Stephan Hartmann 261:Nancy Cartwright 160:Stephan Hartmann 156:Nancy Cartwright 83:Publication date 29: 22: 627: 626: 622: 621: 620: 618: 617: 616: 587: 586: 585: 584: 574: 572: 563: 562: 558: 551: 544: 543: 539: 499: 498: 494: 464: 463: 454: 424: 423: 394: 387: 374: 373: 346: 341: 326: 309: 301: 288: 247:Chapter 8 from 238:Mauricio Suárez 218: 211: 168: 148:Mauricio Suárez 132: 84: 64: 60: 40: 17: 12: 11: 5: 625: 623: 615: 614: 609: 604: 599: 589: 588: 583: 582: 556: 537: 492: 452: 392: 385: 343: 342: 340: 337: 336: 335: 332: 325: 322: 306: 300: 297: 285: 269:interpretative 216: 210:both domains. 208: 203:Mary S. Morgan 167: 164: 131: 128: 120:Mary S. Morgan 109: 108: 106:978-0521650977 103: 97: 96: 93: 89: 88: 85: 82: 79: 78: 73: 69: 68: 55: 51: 50: 47: 43: 42: 38:Mary S. Morgan 35: 31: 30: 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 624: 613: 610: 608: 605: 603: 600: 598: 595: 594: 592: 571: 567: 560: 557: 550: 549: 541: 538: 533: 529: 524: 519: 515: 511: 508:(1): 99–123. 507: 503: 496: 493: 488: 484: 480: 476: 472: 468: 461: 459: 457: 453: 448: 444: 440: 436: 432: 428: 421: 419: 417: 415: 413: 411: 409: 407: 405: 403: 401: 399: 397: 393: 388: 382: 378: 371: 369: 367: 365: 363: 361: 359: 357: 355: 353: 351: 349: 345: 338: 333: 331: 328: 327: 323: 321: 319: 313: 305: 298: 296: 293: 284: 282: 281:index numbers 276: 274: 270: 266: 262: 258: 254: 250: 245: 243: 239: 235: 231: 227: 222: 215: 207: 204: 199: 197: 193: 190: 186: 182: 178: 174: 173:received view 165: 163: 161: 157: 153: 149: 145: 141: 137: 129: 127: 125: 121: 117: 116: 107: 104: 102: 98: 94: 90: 86: 80: 77: 74: 70: 67: 63: 59: 56: 52: 48: 44: 39: 36: 32: 28: 23: 573:. Retrieved 569: 559: 547: 540: 505: 501: 495: 470: 466: 430: 426: 376: 314: 310: 302: 289: 277: 272: 268: 264: 249:Geert Reuten 246: 244:in physics. 230:Ursula Klein 223: 219: 212: 200: 192:Ursula Klein 169: 152:Geert Reuten 144:Ursula Klein 133: 114: 113: 112: 226:Ising model 591:Categories 575:28 January 339:References 532:1879-4920 487:0306-3127 447:1474-0028 299:Reception 196:Chemistry 185:economics 136:economics 72:Publisher 66:Economics 16:1999 book 324:See also 253:exegesis 130:Synopsis 54:Subjects 46:Language 181:physics 166:Content 140:physics 49:English 34:Editors 530:  485:  445:  383:  552:(PDF) 273:force 194:, in 177:logic 92:Pages 577:2024 528:ISSN 483:ISSN 443:ISSN 381:ISBN 290:For 138:and 101:ISBN 87:1999 518:hdl 510:doi 475:doi 435:doi 320:'. 318:STS 255:of 183:or 95:401 593:: 568:. 526:. 516:. 504:. 481:. 471:30 469:. 455:^ 441:. 431:17 429:. 395:^ 347:^ 198:. 162:. 154:, 150:, 126:. 579:. 534:. 520:: 512:: 506:8 489:. 477:: 449:. 437:: 389:. 171:'

Index


Mary S. Morgan
Sociology of quantification
Philosophy of Science
Economics
Cambridge University Press
ISBN
978-0521650977
Mary S. Morgan
Cambridge University Press
economics
physics
Ursula Klein
Mauricio Suárez
Geert Reuten
Nancy Cartwright
Stephan Hartmann
received view
logic
physics
economics
historian of science
Ursula Klein
Chemistry
Mary S. Morgan
Ising model
Ursula Klein
Jöns Jacob Berzelius
Mauricio Suárez
superconductivity

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.