Knowledge (XXG)

Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot

Source đź“ť

219:. He asserts that the "existence of our senses" is "indisputable," and that these senses are thus the principle of all knowledge. He links this idea to a chain of thinking and reflection that eventually leads to the need to communicate, which sets another chain of events in effect. One of his arguments for the origin of communication is that it was necessary for people to protect themselves from the evils of the world and to benefit from each other's knowledge. This communication led to the exchange of ideas that enhanced the ability of individuals to further human knowledge. Additionally, d'Alembert introduces the reader to the types of knowledge people store. The two main types that he describes refer to direct and reflexive knowledge. Direct knowledge is obtained by human senses and reflexive knowledge is derived from direct knowledge. These two types of knowledge lead to the three main types of thinking and their corresponding divisions of human knowledge: 389:, d’Alembert rejects a priori, indemonstrable speculations that lead to error and “intellectual despotism” and assumes a method based on hard facts and evidence (xxxv). A main objective of the “Encyclopedia” was not only to organize a collection of known information, but also to establish a cohesive method of gathering facts and principles yet to be discovered. D’Alembert acknowledges that “it is no less difficult to encompass the infinitely varied branches of human knowledge in a truly unified system,” (5), yet despite this seemingly formidable task, D’Alembert succeeds in fulfilling the purpose of the Encyclopedia, which was to gather all the facets of knowledge into one unified text, and to compile knowledge in a way that it could be standardized and compartmentalized into different categories. With this method, d’Alembert believed the 254:, music and many others. d'Alembert was also greatly influenced by the Cartesian principle of simplicity. In this first part of the book, he describes how the reduction of the principles of a certain science gives them scope and makes them more "fertile" (22). Only by reducing principles can they be understood and related to each other. Ultimately, from a high "vantage point" (47) the philosopher can then view the vast labyrinth of sciences and the arts. d'Alembert then goes on to describe the tree of knowledge and the separation and simultaneous connections between memory, reason, and imagination. He later explains that the ideal universe would be one gigantic truth if one only knew how to view it as such; the assumption that knowledge has intrinsic unity can be seen as the foundation of the project of making the encyclopedia. 291:. He focuses on the importance of ancient knowledge and the ability to understand and build on it. Reference is made that concepts of knowledge could not have advanced as quickly had there not been ancient works to imitate and surpass. He also clarifies that there can be disadvantages to the ability to retrieve information from the past. Noted in the text is the lack of improvement in philosophy in comparison to other advancements due to the ignorant belief that ancient philosophy could not be questioned. d'Alembert claims that it would be ignorant to perceive that everything could be known about a particular subject. Additionally, he makes an attempt to show how individuals could free their minds from the yoke of authority. His use of 182:, scientists all over Europe began to make their own changes in terms of new discoveries, areas they felt required further study, and how they could go about such studies, i.e. their methodology. Many of these new scientists felt that they were rebelling against old forms of science and scientific knowledge, just as the philosophes felt that they were bringing to the world a new way of thinking about humanity and human knowledge. The philosophes were aware of these changes in the field of science, and as such, they fully supported, and arguably adapted, the scientists' new systems of thinking into their philosophical ideas. One can see this in the 163:, and eventually, d'Alembert was a man who was held in very high regard among Europe's intellectuals. Ultimately, d'Alembert's tendency to turn more to history to explain the foundations of science and ethics reflects a general historical trend to seek enlightenment and better understanding of human nature in history. Ultimately, the Discourse defines two ways of approaching ideas, one of which being operations of the "isolated mind" (xli) and the other concerning studies of the origins of truth as a function of the progress of a given society. Although the Discourse derives much of its fundamental principles from men such as 398:, which quantifies knowledge by dividing it into three categories: memory, reason, and imagination. The purpose of this was to place knowledge within general framework that could be added to or expounded upon if necessary. As Richard Schwab, who translated the text, states in the introduction, d’Alembert believed the “Discourse of method” would give mankind the power to independently shape and direct its own destiny. This method provided an answer to the growing demand of the intellectual community of Europe to create a synthesis of information based upon secular and naturalistic principles rather than upon a theological 411:"In vain did some philosophers assert, while suppressing their groans in the midst of sufferings, that pain was not an evil at all. In vain did others place supreme happiness in sensuality-of which they nevertheless deprived themselves through fear of its consequences. All of them would have known our nature better if they had been content to limit their definition of the sovereign good of the present life to the exemption from pain, and to agree that, without hoping to arrive at this sovereign good, we are allowed only to approach it more or less, in proportion to our vigilance and the precautions we take." 299:. He makes clear that all sciences are restricted as much as can be to facts and that opinion influences science as little as possible. d'Alembert states that philosophy is far more effective at the analysis of our perceptions when the "soul is in a state of tranquility", when it is not caught up in passion and emotion (96). He believes that the philosopher is key in furthering the fields of science. The philosopher must be able to stand back and observe science and nature with an impartial eye. Furthermore, the importance of science and the advancements of such intellects as 140:, with whom d'Alembert was known to have been in contact. These men shared a passion for the dissemination of scientific knowledge. And, although this time period would seem unfavorable to such an endeavor, with Europe undergoing massive political upheaval and general instability, the time was ripe for their ideals to take hold. A thriving community of professionals, aristocrats, and clergy became increasingly responsive to the exchange of ideas that came to characterize and serve as the foundation for the cooperative compilation of information in this 357:
other two to build upon itself and further human knowledge as a whole. In context the chart shows a progression of knowledge through the ages, memory being the past, reason being the present, which examines and tries to either build or create new theories based on memory, and imagination which focuses on making new assumptions or theories about things in our human universe.
352:", which divides human understanding into its three constituents: memory, reason, and imagination. The chart then subdivides each of the three major categories into many other categories of human understanding. After his chart d'Alembert goes on to provide a detailed explanation of every division and subdivision apparent in his chart. The chart establishes a complex 202:. D'Alembert puts forth that all men are equal in their sensations, which is the source of their mind. The ultimate distinction of man is primarily intellectual, which overthrows any preconceived connection between social privilege and knowledge. Therefore, the Encyclopedia as a whole speaks to the general public. 356:
of knowledge and the way man has subdivided knowledge into the specific areas he feels they are applicable. It is important to remember that no one of these systems of human knowledge plays a more significant role than any of the others. These systems are designed around the idea that each uses the
331:
is open to changes and additions from others since it is a work of many centuries. In addition, he states that an omission in an encyclopedia is harmful to its substance which differs from an omission in a dictionary. d'Alembert also states the three categories of the Encyclopédie, which are the
189:
D'Alembert's motives behind such an enterprise can ultimately be referenced to one of the ideas that he puts forth in the Discourse, for "liberty of action and thought alone is capable of producing great things, and liberty requires only enlightenment to preserve it from excess" (62). Clerical
262:
Part two of the book provides the reader with an account of the progress of human knowledge in the sequence of memory, imagination and reason. This sequence is different from the one described in Part I, where the sequence is memory, reason, and imagination. It is the sequence a mind left in
393:
could create a system of knowledge that would be unified and systematized, but not so rigid and strict as to impose limits on the search for new facts. A classic example of this systematized approach is the aforementioned
74:
and their philosophy, as well as to give the reader a strong background in the history behind the works of the learned men who contributed to what became the most profound circulation of the knowledge of the time.
270:
Instead of writing in terms of general ideas, d'Alembert provides the dates, places and people responsible for the progress of literary works since the Renaissance leading up to his date. One key example is
186:
itself; d'Alembert attempted to create a method of systematizing and organizing all legitimate information and knowledge as well as make easier and more efficient the unearthing of more knowledge.
263:
isolation or the original generation follows whereas in Part II he describes the progress of human knowledge in the centuries of enlightenment that started from erudition, continued with
336:
and the mechanical arts. He states that it is important that these subcategories remain separate and concludes with the fact that society must judge the Preliminary Discourse to the
151:
was ever created, d'Alembert was actually better known for his scientific and mathematical genius. However, over time, and in part due to his vibrant personality, he befriended
190:
control in the domain of knowledge and intellect was considered detrimental to the progress of human knowledge. Maintaining that the Discourse was ultimately corrosive to
538: 568: 613: 458: 608: 446: 90:, giving forth the idea that man possesses the capability, through his own intelligence and analysis, to alter the conditions of human life. The 603: 422: 349: 574: 348:
At the end of the book, d'Alembert includes a detailed explanation of the system of human knowledge. This includes a chart entitled "
521: 215:
In part one of the book, d'Alembert provides a general introduction to the origin of knowledge, which led to the works found in the
402:(xxxi), and to disseminate knowledge throughout the entire population, no longer being restricted to the wealthy, academic elite. 137: 593: 284: 178:
It is important to note that while the philosophers began the intellectual transformations that became known as the
529: 494: 67: 44:
Encyclopédie ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, par une Société de Gens de lettres
598: 470: 482: 103: 133: 159:
ultimately allowed him to enter the public eye as a philosophe. d'Alembert also became a close ally of
179: 87: 59: 122:" aiming towards the same progressive goals of the Enlightenment. Three of these major contemporary 56: 550: 527:
Fort, Bernadette; Sheriff, Mary; Thompson, James (1994). "Introduction: The Editorial Function".
98:
in reference to past and recent discoveries. Such a compilation of human knowledge would be both
52: 128:
that undoubtedly contributed to the guiding philosophies and beliefs of the "Discourse" include
542: 517: 288: 275:, who the author lauds as both an excellent philosopher and mathematician. His application of 272: 164: 156: 152: 94:
constituted a demand of the intellectual community for a refinement of all of the branches of
323:
Part three of the book concludes by detailing the important attributes of the writing of the
292: 199: 434: 43: 264: 587: 487: 475: 427: 300: 129: 115: 38: 382: 333: 304: 191: 119: 236: 195: 172: 124: 463: 451: 378: 374: 312: 232: 168: 48: 546: 516:. Trans. Richard N. Schwab. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1995. 399: 353: 308: 240: 95: 579:
Encyclopedia of Diderot & d'Alembert Collaborative Translation Project
499: 280: 107: 554: 439: 327:
and by mentioning important contributors. d'Alembert discusses how the
276: 247: 224: 160: 99: 251: 228: 220: 296: 47:, a collaborative collection of all the known branches of the 194:
authority and privilege paved the way for the evolution of
70:
to describe the structure of the articles included in the
246:
From these divisions spring smaller subdivisions such as
295:
provides a more philosophical base for the existence of
84:
The Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot
373:
marked a shift from Descartes’ rationalism toward the
175:
sense, the effect of historical experience is vital.
118:, was actually a result of collaboration with other " 514:
Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot
86:is arguably one of the best introductions to the 539:American Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies 239:," (50) or imitation of Nature, which produces 8: 459:An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 16:Introductory article to the Encyclopedie 447:An Essay Concerning Human Understanding 287:, provided an excellent tool for the 7: 423:Figurative system of human knowledge 396:figurative system of human knowledge 350:Figurative System of Human Knowledge 235:; and what d'Alembert refers to as " 35:Discours PrĂ©liminaire des Éditeurs 14: 614:Philosophy of science literature 609:Modern philosophical literature 1: 604:French-language encyclopedias 267:, and reached to philosophy. 285:Cartesian coordinate system 138:Étienne Bonnot de Condillac 630: 530:Eighteenth-Century Studies 512:d'Alembert, Jean Le Rond. 495:Dictionnaire Philosophique 315:and others are explained. 171:and Condillac in a purely 110:as the primary basis. The 344:System of Human Knowledge 223:, which corresponds with 231:, which is the basis of 483:Critique of Pure Reason 68:Jean Le Rond d'Alembert 471:What is Enlightenment? 114:, although created by 134:Jean-Jacques Rousseau 64:Preliminary Discourse 22:Preliminary Discourse 594:Age of Enlightenment 283:, also known as the 180:French Enlightenment 88:French Enlightenment 55:of the 18th century 575:English translation 37:) is the primer to 365:The method of the 289:physical sciences 155:, whose powerful 153:Madame du Deffand 621: 558: 227:; reflection or 629: 628: 624: 623: 622: 620: 619: 618: 584: 583: 565: 526: 509: 418: 408: 363: 346: 321: 293:deductive logic 260: 213: 208: 200:Western culture 106:, discrediting 81: 66:was written by 17: 12: 11: 5: 627: 625: 617: 616: 611: 606: 601: 596: 586: 585: 582: 581: 572: 564: 563:External links 561: 560: 559: 524: 508: 505: 504: 503: 491: 479: 467: 455: 443: 431: 417: 414: 413: 412: 407: 404: 362: 359: 345: 342: 332:sciences, the 320: 317: 273:RenĂ© Descartes 265:belles-lettres 259: 256: 212: 209: 207: 204: 198:principles in 165:RenĂ© Descartes 120:men of letters 80: 77: 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 626: 615: 612: 610: 607: 605: 602: 600: 597: 595: 592: 591: 589: 580: 576: 573: 571:at Wikisource 570: 569:Original Text 567: 566: 562: 556: 552: 548: 544: 540: 536: 532: 531: 525: 523: 522:0-226-13476-8 519: 515: 511: 510: 506: 501: 497: 496: 492: 489: 488:Immanuel Kant 485: 484: 480: 477: 476:Immanuel Kant 473: 472: 468: 465: 461: 460: 456: 453: 449: 448: 444: 441: 437: 436: 432: 429: 425: 424: 420: 419: 415: 410: 409: 405: 403: 401: 397: 392: 388: 384: 380: 376: 372: 368: 360: 358: 355: 351: 343: 341: 339: 335: 330: 326: 318: 316: 314: 310: 306: 302: 301:Francis Bacon 298: 294: 290: 286: 282: 278: 274: 268: 266: 257: 255: 253: 249: 244: 242: 238: 234: 230: 226: 222: 218: 210: 205: 203: 201: 197: 193: 187: 185: 181: 176: 174: 170: 166: 162: 158: 154: 150: 145: 143: 139: 135: 131: 130:Denis Diderot 127: 126: 121: 117: 113: 109: 105: 101: 97: 93: 89: 85: 78: 76: 73: 69: 65: 61: 60:Enlightenment 58: 54: 50: 46: 45: 40: 39:Denis Diderot 36: 32: 31: 27: 23: 599:EncyclopĂ©die 578: 534: 528: 513: 493: 481: 469: 457: 445: 435:EncyclopĂ©die 433: 421: 395: 390: 386: 383:Isaac Newton 371:Encyclopedia 370: 366: 364: 361:Significance 347: 340:of Diderot. 338:Encyclopedia 337: 334:liberal arts 329:EncyclopĂ©die 328: 325:EncyclopĂ©die 324: 322: 305:Isaac Newton 269: 261: 245: 217:EncyclopĂ©die 216: 214: 192:hierarchical 188: 183: 177: 173:metaphysical 148: 146: 142:Encyclopedia 141: 123: 111: 104:naturalistic 92:Encyclopedia 91: 83: 82: 72:EncyclopĂ©die 71: 63: 42: 34: 29: 26:Encyclopedia 25: 21: 20: 18: 391:philosophes 237:imagination 196:egalitarian 147:Before the 125:philosophes 588:Categories 507:References 464:David Hume 452:John Locke 428:d'Alembert 379:John Locke 375:empiricism 313:John Locke 233:Philosophy 169:John Locke 116:d'Alembert 79:Background 547:1086-315X 541:: i–iii. 400:teleology 387:Discourse 385:. In the 367:Discourse 354:genealogy 309:Descartes 241:Fine Arts 184:Discourse 149:Discourse 112:Discourse 96:knowledge 500:Voltaire 416:See also 369:and the 319:Part III 281:geometry 108:theology 53:sciences 577:at the 555:2739217 440:Diderot 277:algebra 258:Part II 248:physics 225:History 206:Summary 161:Diderot 100:secular 30:Diderot 24:to the 553:  545:  520:  406:Quotes 252:poetry 229:reason 221:memory 211:Part I 136:, and 62:. The 57:French 551:JSTOR 537:(1). 157:salon 543:ISSN 518:ISBN 381:and 102:and 51:and 49:arts 19:The 377:of 297:God 279:to 41:'s 28:of 590:: 549:. 535:28 533:. 498:, 486:, 474:, 462:, 450:, 438:, 426:, 311:, 307:, 303:, 250:, 243:. 167:, 144:. 132:, 557:. 502:. 490:. 478:. 466:. 454:. 442:. 430:. 33:(

Index

Denis Diderot
Encyclopédie ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, par une Société de Gens de lettres
arts
sciences
French
Enlightenment
Jean Le Rond d'Alembert
French Enlightenment
knowledge
secular
naturalistic
theology
d'Alembert
men of letters
philosophes
Denis Diderot
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
Étienne Bonnot de Condillac
Madame du Deffand
salon
Diderot
René Descartes
John Locke
metaphysical
French Enlightenment
hierarchical
egalitarian
Western culture
memory
History

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑