Knowledge

Principle of permanence

Source đź“ť

1033: 110:
Conversely, if we discover an equivalent form in Arithmetical Algebra or any other subordinate science, when the symbols are general in form though specific in their nature, the same must be an equivalent form, when the symbols are general in their nature as well as in their
662: 497: 236: 557: 1015: 988: 688: 359: 292: 417: 385: 318: 597: 577: 173:
One of the main uses of the principle of permanence is to show that a functional equation that holds for the real numbers also holds for the complex numbers.
47:, the principle of permanence was considered an important tool in mathematical arguments. In modern mathematics, arguments have instead been supplanted by 1074: 1098: 942: 832: 104:
Whatever form is Algebraically equivalent to another, when expressed in general symbols, must be true, whatever those symbols denote.
1093: 249:. By the principle of permanence for functions of two variables, this suggests that it holds for all complex numbers as well. 602: 76: 1067: 458: 67:, which state that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. 816: 712: 934: 1060: 1040: 179: 17: 888: 447:'s extensions of the natural numbers beyond infinity, neither satisfies both properties simultaneously. 162: 154: 144: 694:
Hence both of these, the early rigorous infinite number systems, violate the principle of permanence.
56: 29: 509: 503: 64: 993: 859: 802: 737: 452: 48: 899:. Vol. 1. L'Imprimerie Royale, Debure frères, Libraires du Roi et de la Bibliothèque du Roi 149: 938: 133: 973: 892: 667: 326: 259: 869: 747: 157:" to describe (and criticize) a method of argument used by 18th century mathematicians like 129: 44: 390: 432: 364: 297: 1044: 927: 582: 562: 440: 428: 424: 158: 121: 117: 1087: 33: 815:
Wolfram, Stephen. "Chapter 12, Section 9, Footnote: Generalization in mathematics".
711:
Wolfram, Stephen. "Chapter 12, Section 9, Footnote: Generalization in mathematics".
444: 909: 913: 436: 239: 125: 874: 769: 752: 52: 455:, addition is left-cancellative, but no longer commutative. For example, 60: 799:
On Symbolical Algebra and its Applications to the Geometry of Position
37: 32:
like addition and multiplication should behave consistently in every
864: 850:
Toader, Iulian D. (2021), "Permanence as a principle of practice",
742: 728:
Toader, Iulian D. (2021), "Permanence as a principle of practice",
1032: 506:, addition is commutative, but no longer left-cancellative, since 59:. Additionally, the principle has been formalized into a class of 43:
Before the advent of modern mathematics and its emphasis on the
929:
Georg Cantor: his mathematics and philosophy of the infinite
51:
built upon axioms, and the principle is instead used as a
252:
For a counter example, consider the following properties
87:
132. Let us again recur to this principle or law of the
1048: 657:{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}+1=\aleph _{0}=\aleph _{0}+2} 996: 976: 670: 605: 585: 565: 512: 461: 393: 367: 329: 300: 262: 182: 1009: 982: 926: 682: 656: 591: 571: 551: 491: 411: 379: 353: 312: 286: 230: 1017:in ordinal and cardinal arithmetic, respectively. 774:History of Science and Mathematics Stack Exchange 165:that was similar to the Principle of Permanence. 897:Cours d'Analyse de l'Ecole royale polytechnique 764: 762: 492:{\displaystyle 3+\omega =\omega \neq \omega +3} 91:, and consider it when stated in the form of a 1068: 8: 546: 534: 970:The smallest infinite number is denoted by 323:left-cancellative property of addition: if 1075: 1061: 789:(J. & J. J. Deighton, 1830). — 1001: 995: 975: 873: 863: 751: 741: 669: 642: 629: 610: 604: 584: 564: 511: 460: 392: 366: 328: 299: 261: 216: 206: 187: 181: 26:law of the permanence of equivalent forms 38:extensions to established number systems 703: 793:(2nd ed., Scripta Mathematica): Vol.1 7: 1029: 1027: 961:, UTM Series, Springer-Verlag, 2001c 833:"Hankel, Hermann | Encyclopedia.com" 231:{\displaystyle e^{s+t}-e^{s}e^{t}=0} 116:The principle was later revised by 998: 639: 626: 607: 14: 443:numbers. However, when following 1031: 139:Around the same time period as 75:The principle was described by 552:{\displaystyle x+y=max\{x,y\}} 89:permanence of equivalent forms 1: 801:(1845). Quote from 1830 ed., 423:Both properties hold for all 36:, especially when developing 1099:History of mathematics stubs 1047:. You can help Knowledge by 176:As an example, the equation 1010:{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}} 256:commutativity of addition: 1115: 1026: 925:Dauben, Joseph W. (1979), 599:is infinite. For example, 770:"Principle of Permanence" 935:Harvard University Press 875:10.1016/j.hm.2020.08.001 753:10.1016/j.hm.2020.08.001 83:(emphasis in original): 1039:This article about the 983:{\displaystyle \omega } 683:{\displaystyle 1\neq 2} 354:{\displaystyle x+y=x+z} 287:{\displaystyle x+y=y+x} 153:, which used the term " 22:principle of permanence 1094:History of mathematics 1041:history of mathematics 1011: 984: 889:Cauchy, Augustin-Louis 684: 658: 593: 573: 553: 493: 413: 381: 355: 314: 288: 232: 114: 18:history of mathematics 1012: 985: 818:A New Kind of Science 791:A Treatise on Algebra 787:A Treatise on Algebra 714:A New Kind of Science 685: 659: 594: 574: 554: 494: 414: 412:{\displaystyle x,y,z} 382: 356: 315: 289: 233: 155:generality of algebra 145:Augustin-Louis Cauchy 141:A Treatise of Algebra 85: 81:A Treatise of Algebra 994: 974: 893:"Analyse AlgĂ©brique" 852:Historia Mathematica 837:www.encyclopedia.com 795:Arithmetical Algebra 730:Historia Mathematica 668: 603: 583: 563: 510: 459: 391: 365: 327: 298: 260: 180: 57:algebraic structures 55:for discovering new 30:algebraic operations 28:, was the idea that 504:cardinal arithmetic 380:{\displaystyle y=z} 313:{\displaystyle x,y} 65:transfer principles 1007: 980: 680: 654: 589: 569: 549: 489: 453:ordinal arithmetic 409: 377: 351: 310: 284: 228: 1056: 1055: 944:978-0-691-02447-9 592:{\displaystyle y} 572:{\displaystyle x} 134:Alfred Pringsheim 1106: 1077: 1070: 1063: 1035: 1028: 1018: 1016: 1014: 1013: 1008: 1006: 1005: 989: 987: 986: 981: 968: 962: 959:Complex Analysis 955: 949: 947: 932: 922: 916: 907: 905: 904: 885: 879: 878: 877: 867: 847: 841: 840: 829: 823: 822: 812: 806: 784: 778: 777: 766: 757: 756: 755: 745: 725: 719: 718: 708: 689: 687: 686: 681: 663: 661: 660: 655: 647: 646: 634: 633: 615: 614: 598: 596: 595: 590: 578: 576: 575: 570: 558: 556: 555: 550: 498: 496: 495: 490: 418: 416: 415: 410: 386: 384: 383: 378: 360: 358: 357: 352: 319: 317: 316: 311: 293: 291: 290: 285: 237: 235: 234: 229: 221: 220: 211: 210: 198: 197: 130:Hermann Schubert 45:axiomatic method 1114: 1113: 1109: 1108: 1107: 1105: 1104: 1103: 1084: 1083: 1082: 1081: 1024: 1022: 1021: 997: 992: 991: 972: 971: 969: 965: 956: 952: 945: 924: 923: 919: 902: 900: 887: 886: 882: 849: 848: 844: 831: 830: 826: 821:. p. 1168. 814: 813: 809: 785: 781: 768: 767: 760: 727: 726: 722: 717:. p. 1168. 710: 709: 705: 700: 666: 665: 638: 625: 606: 601: 600: 581: 580: 561: 560: 508: 507: 457: 456: 389: 388: 363: 362: 325: 324: 296: 295: 258: 257: 212: 202: 183: 178: 177: 171: 150:Cours d'Analyse 120:and adopted by 73: 49:rigorous proofs 12: 11: 5: 1112: 1110: 1102: 1101: 1096: 1086: 1085: 1080: 1079: 1072: 1065: 1057: 1054: 1053: 1036: 1020: 1019: 1004: 1000: 979: 963: 950: 943: 917: 880: 842: 824: 807: 797:(1842), Vol.2 779: 758: 720: 702: 701: 699: 696: 692: 691: 679: 676: 673: 653: 650: 645: 641: 637: 632: 628: 624: 621: 618: 613: 609: 588: 568: 548: 545: 542: 539: 536: 533: 530: 527: 524: 521: 518: 515: 500: 488: 485: 482: 479: 476: 473: 470: 467: 464: 421: 420: 408: 405: 402: 399: 396: 376: 373: 370: 350: 347: 344: 341: 338: 335: 332: 321: 309: 306: 303: 283: 280: 277: 274: 271: 268: 265: 227: 224: 219: 215: 209: 205: 201: 196: 193: 190: 186: 170: 167: 136:, and others. 122:Giuseppe Peano 118:Hermann Hankel 77:George Peacock 72: 69: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1111: 1100: 1097: 1095: 1092: 1091: 1089: 1078: 1073: 1071: 1066: 1064: 1059: 1058: 1052: 1050: 1046: 1042: 1037: 1034: 1030: 1025: 1002: 977: 967: 964: 960: 954: 951: 946: 940: 936: 931: 930: 921: 918: 915: 911: 898: 894: 890: 884: 881: 876: 871: 866: 861: 857: 853: 846: 843: 838: 834: 828: 825: 820: 819: 811: 808: 804: 800: 796: 792: 788: 783: 780: 775: 771: 765: 763: 759: 754: 749: 744: 739: 735: 731: 724: 721: 716: 715: 707: 704: 697: 695: 677: 674: 671: 651: 648: 643: 635: 630: 622: 619: 616: 611: 586: 566: 543: 540: 537: 531: 528: 525: 522: 519: 516: 513: 505: 501: 486: 483: 480: 477: 474: 471: 468: 465: 462: 454: 450: 449: 448: 446: 442: 438: 434: 430: 426: 406: 403: 400: 397: 394: 374: 371: 368: 348: 345: 342: 339: 336: 333: 330: 322: 307: 304: 301: 281: 278: 275: 272: 269: 266: 263: 255: 254: 253: 250: 248: 244: 241: 238:hold for all 225: 222: 217: 213: 207: 203: 199: 194: 191: 188: 184: 174: 168: 166: 164: 160: 156: 152: 151: 146: 142: 137: 135: 131: 127: 123: 119: 113: 112: 107: 105: 100: 98: 94: 90: 84: 82: 78: 70: 68: 66: 62: 58: 54: 50: 46: 41: 39: 35: 34:number system 31: 27: 23: 19: 1049:expanding it 1038: 1023: 966: 958: 957:Gamelin, T. 953: 928: 920: 910:Free version 901:. Retrieved 896: 883: 855: 851: 845: 836: 827: 817: 810: 798: 794: 790: 786: 782: 773: 733: 729: 723: 713: 706: 693: 445:Georg Cantor 422: 251: 246: 242: 240:real numbers 175: 172: 169:Applications 148: 140: 138: 115: 109: 108: 103: 101: 99:proportion. 96: 92: 88: 86: 80: 79:in his book 74: 42: 25: 21: 15: 914:archive.org 1088:Categories 933:, Boston: 903:2015-11-07 865:2408.08547 743:2408.08547 698:References 387:, for all 147:published 126:Ernst Mach 999:ℵ 978:ω 858:: 77–94, 736:: 77–94, 675:≠ 640:ℵ 627:ℵ 608:ℵ 559:whenever 481:ω 478:≠ 475:ω 469:ω 200:− 53:heuristic 891:(1821). 433:rational 294:for all 163:Lagrange 97:converse 61:theorems 441:complex 429:integer 425:natural 361:, then 71:History 63:called 16:In the 941:  803:p. 104 664:, but 439:, and 93:direct 20:, the 1043:is a 860:arXiv 738:arXiv 159:Euler 111:form. 24:, or 1045:stub 990:and 939:ISBN 437:real 161:and 95:and 912:at 870:doi 748:doi 579:or 502:In 451:In 1090:: 937:, 908:* 895:. 868:, 856:54 854:, 835:. 772:. 761:^ 746:, 734:54 732:, 435:, 431:, 427:, 245:, 143:, 132:, 128:, 124:, 106:" 40:. 1076:e 1069:t 1062:v 1051:. 1003:0 948:. 906:. 872:: 862:: 839:. 805:. 776:. 750:: 740:: 690:. 678:2 672:1 652:2 649:+ 644:0 636:= 631:0 623:= 620:1 617:+ 612:0 587:y 567:x 547:} 544:y 541:, 538:x 535:{ 532:x 529:a 526:m 523:= 520:y 517:+ 514:x 499:. 487:3 484:+ 472:= 466:+ 463:3 419:. 407:z 404:, 401:y 398:, 395:x 375:z 372:= 369:y 349:z 346:+ 343:x 340:= 337:y 334:+ 331:x 320:, 308:y 305:, 302:x 282:x 279:+ 276:y 273:= 270:y 267:+ 264:x 247:t 243:s 226:0 223:= 218:t 214:e 208:s 204:e 195:t 192:+ 189:s 185:e 102:"

Index

history of mathematics
algebraic operations
number system
extensions to established number systems
axiomatic method
rigorous proofs
heuristic
algebraic structures
theorems
transfer principles
George Peacock
Hermann Hankel
Giuseppe Peano
Ernst Mach
Hermann Schubert
Alfred Pringsheim
Augustin-Louis Cauchy
Cours d'Analyse
generality of algebra
Euler
Lagrange
real numbers
natural
integer
rational
real
complex
Georg Cantor
ordinal arithmetic
cardinal arithmetic

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑