Knowledge (XXG)

Natural slavery

Source 📝

62:, Aristotle describes a natural slave as "anyone who, while being human, is by nature not his own but of someone else" and further states "he is of someone else when, while being human, he is a piece of property; and a piece of property is a tool for action separate from its owner." From this, Aristotle defines natural slavery in two phases. The first is the natural slave's existence and characteristics. The second is the natural slave in society and in interaction with their master. According to Aristotle, natural slaves' main features and include being pieces of property, tools for actions, and belonging to others. 117:
definition of the "barbarian" and the natural slave did not apply to the Indians, who were fully capable of reason and should be brought to Christianity without force or coercion. SepĂșlveda reasoned that the enslavement of natives was a result of war: the "superior" was dominating the "inferior", and the Spaniards had every right to do so.
81:
Aristotle's work has come under controversy and criticism in recent years. According to Darrell Dobbs, there is a "general consensus that the formulation of Aristotle's account of slavery is riddled with inconsistency and incoherence." Other scholars have argued that the state of natural slavery is
73:
those who are as different as the soul from the body or man from beast—and they are in this state if their work is the use of the body, and if this is the best that can come from them—are slaves by nature. For them it is better to be ruled in accordance with this sort of rule, if such is the case
116:
met in Spain for a debate on the rationalization of native American enslavement and its morality based on Aristotle's idea of natural slavery. SepĂșlveda defended the position of the New World colonists, claiming that the Amerindians were "natural slaves." Las Casas countered that Aristotle's
100:
During the 16th century, as the Americas began to be colonized, the debate over the enslavement of the native peoples grew. Many colonizers supported enslavement and went to great lengths to morally justify it.
412:
Moreiras, Alberto (2000-01). "Ten Notes on Primitive Imperial Accumulation: GinĂ©s de SepĂșlveda, Las Casas, FernĂĄndez de Oviedo". Interventions. 2 (3): 343–363. doi:10.1080/13698010020019181. ISSN 1369-801X.
69:, Aristotle addresses the questions of whether slavery can be natural or whether all slavery is contrary to nature and whether it is better for some people to be slaves. He concludes that 78:
It is not advantageous for one to be held in slavery who is not a natural slave, Aristotle contends, claiming that such a condition is sustained solely by force and results in enmity.
105:
was in favor of peacefully converting native peoples without enslaving them. Las Casas protested the treatment of natives by Spaniards, and in 1520 was granted an audience with the
433: 367: 350: 113: 106: 362:
1484-1566., Casas, BartolomĂ© de las, (1996). The devastation of the Indies : a brief account. Hopkins Univ. Press.
345:
1484-1566., Casas, BartolomĂ© de las, (1996). The devastation of the Indies : a brief account. Hopkins Univ. Press.
131: 146: 102: 311:
Rodriguez, Philippe-André (2016). "L'impérialisme institutionnel et la question de la race chez Aristote".
438: 241: 188: 141: 58: 32: 37: 328: 293: 285: 219: 94: 363: 346: 151: 45: 428: 320: 277: 211: 93:
disagreed with the Aristotelian concept of natural slavery, as it was expressed in Seneca's
268:
Dobbs, Darrell (1994). "Natural Right and the Problem of Aristotle's Defense of Slavery".
422: 332: 297: 223: 396: 324: 202:
Karbowski, Joseph (2013). "Aristotle's Scientific Inquiry Into Natural Slavery".
401:
Ex Post Facto: Journal of the History Students at San Francisco State University
126: 236: 183: 27: 215: 90: 82:
ultimately alterable, since Aristotle's conception of nature is as well.
289: 170:
Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery,"
136: 109:(Charles I of Spain). He asked instead for their peaceful conversion. 281: 41: 386:, 4th ed. University of California Press, Berkeley: 1992. 16:
Aristotle's belief that some people are slaves by nature
397:"The Las Casas-SepĂșlveda Controversy: 1550-1551" 8: 378: 376: 163: 7: 204:Journal of the History of Philosophy 51: 40:, while others are slaves solely by 14: 52:Aristotle's discourse on slavery 174:15, no. 3 (Aug. 1987): 390-410. 74:for the other things mentioned. 36:that some people are slaves by 26:) is the argument set forth in 1: 325:10.1080/13507486.2016.1154927 112:In April 1550, Las Casas and 107:Holy Roman Emperor Charles V 455: 313:European Review of History 132:Natural order (philosophy) 395:Bonar Ludwig Hernandez, " 384:The Epic of Latin America 147:Slavery in ancient Greece 434:Philosophy of Aristotle 270:The Journal of Politics 114:Juan GinĂ©s de SepĂșlveda 103:BartolomĂ© de las Casas 76: 216:10.1353/hph.2013.0067 71: 142:Slavery and religion 24:Aristotelian slavery 403:10 (2001): 95–104. 370:. OCLC 315061719 353:. OCLC 315061719. 152:Valladolid debate 65:In book I of the 56:In his work, the 446: 413: 410: 404: 393: 387: 380: 371: 360: 354: 343: 337: 336: 308: 302: 301: 265: 259: 252: 246: 234: 228: 227: 199: 193: 181: 175: 172:Political Theory 168: 454: 453: 449: 448: 447: 445: 444: 443: 419: 418: 417: 416: 411: 407: 394: 390: 381: 374: 361: 357: 344: 340: 310: 309: 305: 282:10.2307/2132346 267: 266: 262: 253: 249: 235: 231: 201: 200: 196: 182: 178: 169: 165: 160: 123: 97:and elsewhere. 88: 54: 20:Natural slavery 17: 12: 11: 5: 452: 450: 442: 441: 436: 431: 421: 420: 415: 414: 405: 388: 382:Crow, John A. 372: 355: 338: 319:(4): 751–767. 303: 260: 247: 229: 210:(3): 331–353. 194: 176: 162: 161: 159: 156: 155: 154: 149: 144: 139: 134: 129: 122: 119: 87: 84: 53: 50: 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 451: 440: 437: 435: 432: 430: 427: 426: 424: 409: 406: 402: 398: 392: 389: 385: 379: 377: 373: 369: 365: 359: 356: 352: 348: 342: 339: 334: 330: 326: 322: 318: 314: 307: 304: 299: 295: 291: 287: 283: 279: 275: 271: 264: 261: 258:, 1255b11–15. 257: 251: 248: 245:, 1254b16–21. 244: 243: 238: 233: 230: 225: 221: 217: 213: 209: 205: 198: 195: 192:, 1254b16–21. 191: 190: 185: 180: 177: 173: 167: 164: 157: 153: 150: 148: 145: 143: 140: 138: 135: 133: 130: 128: 125: 124: 120: 118: 115: 110: 108: 104: 98: 96: 92: 91:Stoic thought 85: 83: 79: 75: 70: 68: 63: 61: 60: 49: 47: 43: 39: 35: 34: 29: 25: 21: 408: 400: 391: 383: 358: 341: 316: 312: 306: 276:(1): 69–94. 273: 269: 263: 255: 250: 240: 232: 207: 203: 197: 187: 179: 171: 166: 111: 99: 89: 80: 77: 72: 66: 64: 57: 55: 31: 23: 19: 18: 439:Natural law 254:Aristotle, 127:Natural law 423:Categories 368:0801844304 351:0801844304 158:References 46:convention 333:148351591 298:154361056 237:Aristotle 224:143700270 184:Aristotle 95:Letter 47 86:Influence 28:Aristotle 256:Politics 242:Politics 189:Politics 121:See also 67:Politics 59:Politics 33:Politics 429:Slavery 290:2132346 137:Slavery 366:  349:  331:  296:  288:  222:  38:nature 329:S2CID 294:S2CID 286:JSTOR 220:S2CID 364:ISBN 347:ISBN 22:(or 399:," 321:doi 278:doi 212:doi 186:, 44:or 42:law 30:'s 425:: 375:^ 327:. 317:23 315:. 292:. 284:. 274:56 272:. 239:, 218:. 208:51 206:. 48:. 335:. 323:: 300:. 280:: 226:. 214::

Index

Aristotle
Politics
nature
law
convention
Politics
Stoic thought
Letter 47
Bartolomé de las Casas
Holy Roman Emperor Charles V
Juan GinĂ©s de SepĂșlveda
Natural law
Natural order (philosophy)
Slavery
Slavery and religion
Slavery in ancient Greece
Valladolid debate
Aristotle
Politics
doi
10.1353/hph.2013.0067
S2CID
143700270
Aristotle
Politics
doi
10.2307/2132346
JSTOR
2132346
S2CID

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑