Knowledge (XXG)

Geometric logic

Source 📝

259:
There are many examples of coherent/geometric theories: all algebraic theories, such as group theory and ring theory, all essentially algebraic theories, such as category theory, the theory of fields, the theory of local rings, lattice theory, projective geometry, the theory of separably closed local
280:
Effective theorem-proving for coherent theories can, with (in relation to resolution) relative ease and clarity, be automated. As noted by Bezem et al ...the absence of Skolemisation (introduction of new function symbols) is no real hardship, and the non-conversion to clausal form allows the
200: 202:
where I and J are disjoint collections of formulae indices that each may be infinite and the formulae φ are either atoms or negations of atoms. If all the axioms are finite (i.e., for each axiom, both I and J are finite), the theory is coherent.
55: 230:
such as G3c, special coherent implications as axioms can be converted directly to inference rules without affecting the admissibility of the structural rules (Weakening, Contraction and Cut);
316: 277:, where D is required to be an atom; in fact, they generalise the “clauses” of disjunctive logic programs, where D is allowed to be a disjunction of atoms. 240:
Coherent implications form sequents that give a Glivenko class. In this case, the result, known as the first-order Barr’s Theorem, states that if each
195:{\displaystyle \bigwedge _{i\in I}\phi _{i,1}\vee \dots \vee \phi _{i,n_{i}}\implies \bigvee _{j\in J}\phi _{j,1}\vee \dots \vee \phi _{j,m_{j}}} 398: 363: 263:
Coherent/geometric theories are preserved by pullback along geometric morphisms between topoi (Maclane & Moerdijk 1992, chapter X);
351: 222:
list eight consequences of the above theorem that explain its significance (omitting footnotes and most references):
321: 40:
tractable. Geometric logic is capable of expressing many mathematical theories and has close connections to
52:
A theory of first-order logic is geometric if it is can be axiomatised using only axioms of the form
414: 260:
rings (aka “strictly Henselian local rings”) and the infinitary theory of torsion abelian groups;
437: 394: 359: 274: 234: 29: 386: 369: 338: 330: 227: 373: 37: 442: 419: 431: 270: 237:
rules in a certain simple form in which only atomic formulas play a critical part”;
41: 266:
Filtered colimits in Set of models of a coherent theory T are also models of T;
390: 21: 377:(Two volumes, Oxford Logic Guides 43 & 44, 3rd volume in preparation) 334: 343: 233:
In similar terms, coherent theories are “the theories expressible by
33: 281:
structure of ordinary mathematical arguments to be better retained.
256:
0 is classically provable then it is intuitionistically provable;
211:
Every first-order theory has a coherent conservative extension.
269:
Special coherent implications ∀x. C ⊃ D generalise the
58: 244:i: 0≤i≤n is a coherent implication and the sequent 356:Sketches of an Elephant: A Topos Theory Compendium 194: 415:"Why is a geometric theory called "geometric"?" 381:Maclane, Saunders Mac; Moerdijk, Ieke (1992), 298: 219: 8: 127: 123: 342: 184: 173: 148: 132: 115: 104: 79: 63: 57: 291: 317:"Geometrisation of first-order logic" 7: 315:Dyckhoff, Roy; Negri, Sara (2015), 14: 124: 1: 383:Sheaves in Geometry and Logic 358:, Oxford University Press, 299:Dyckhoff & Negri (2015) 220:Dyckhoff & Negri (2015) 459: 322:Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 391:10.1007/978-1-4612-0927-0 16:In mathematical logic, 196: 197: 423:. November 15, 2020. 385:, Springer: Berlin, 329:(2): 123–163, 226:In the context of a 56: 301:, pp. 124–125. 38:proof-theoretically 28:, a restriction of 335:10.1017/bsl.2015.7 192: 143: 74: 24:generalisation of 400:978-1-4612-0927-0 365:978-0-19-852496-0 275:logic programming 235:natural deduction 128: 59: 30:first-order logic 450: 424: 403: 376: 352:Johnstone, Peter 347: 346: 302: 296: 228:sequent calculus 201: 199: 198: 193: 191: 190: 189: 188: 159: 158: 142: 122: 121: 120: 119: 90: 89: 73: 458: 457: 453: 452: 451: 449: 448: 447: 428: 427: 413: 410: 408:Further reading 401: 380: 366: 350: 314: 311: 306: 305: 297: 293: 288: 217: 209: 180: 169: 144: 111: 100: 75: 54: 53: 50: 18:geometric logic 12: 11: 5: 456: 454: 446: 445: 440: 430: 429: 426: 425: 420:Stack Exchange 409: 406: 405: 404: 399: 378: 364: 348: 310: 307: 304: 303: 290: 289: 287: 284: 283: 282: 278: 267: 264: 261: 257: 238: 231: 216: 213: 208: 205: 187: 183: 179: 176: 172: 168: 165: 162: 157: 154: 151: 147: 141: 138: 135: 131: 126: 118: 114: 110: 107: 103: 99: 96: 93: 88: 85: 82: 78: 72: 69: 66: 62: 49: 46: 26:coherent logic 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 455: 444: 441: 439: 436: 435: 433: 422: 421: 416: 412: 411: 407: 402: 396: 392: 388: 384: 379: 375: 371: 367: 361: 357: 353: 349: 345: 340: 336: 332: 328: 324: 323: 318: 313: 312: 308: 300: 295: 292: 285: 279: 276: 272: 268: 265: 262: 258: 255: 251: 247: 243: 239: 236: 232: 229: 225: 224: 223: 221: 214: 212: 206: 204: 185: 181: 177: 174: 170: 166: 163: 160: 155: 152: 149: 145: 139: 136: 133: 129: 116: 112: 108: 105: 101: 97: 94: 91: 86: 83: 80: 76: 70: 67: 64: 60: 47: 45: 43: 39: 35: 31: 27: 23: 19: 418: 382: 355: 326: 320: 309:Bibliography 294: 271:Horn clauses 253: 249: 245: 241: 218: 215:Significance 210: 51: 42:topos theory 25: 17: 15: 248:1, . . . , 48:Definitions 432:Categories 374:1071.18002 344:10023/6818 22:infinitary 171:ϕ 167:∨ 164:⋯ 161:∨ 146:ϕ 137:∈ 130:⋁ 125:⟹ 102:ϕ 98:∨ 95:⋯ 92:∨ 77:ϕ 68:∈ 61:⋀ 438:Geometry 354:(2002), 36:that is 207:Theorem 32:due to 397:  372:  362:  34:Skolem 20:is an 443:Logic 286:Notes 273:from 395:ISBN 360:ISBN 252:n ⇒ 387:doi 370:Zbl 339:hdl 331:doi 434:: 417:. 393:, 368:, 337:, 327:21 325:, 319:, 44:. 389:: 341:: 333:: 254:I 250:I 246:I 242:I 186:j 182:m 178:, 175:j 156:1 153:, 150:j 140:J 134:j 117:i 113:n 109:, 106:i 87:1 84:, 81:i 71:I 65:i

Index

infinitary
first-order logic
Skolem
proof-theoretically
topos theory
Dyckhoff & Negri (2015)
sequent calculus
natural deduction
Horn clauses
logic programming
Dyckhoff & Negri (2015)
"Geometrisation of first-order logic"
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic
doi
10.1017/bsl.2015.7
hdl
10023/6818
Johnstone, Peter
ISBN
978-0-19-852496-0
Zbl
1071.18002
doi
10.1007/978-1-4612-0927-0
ISBN
978-1-4612-0927-0
"Why is a geometric theory called "geometric"?"
Stack Exchange
Categories
Geometry

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.