Knowledge (XXG)

Halpern–Läuchli theorem

Source 📝

429: 556: 672: 222: 43:
is false. It is often called the Halpern–Läuchli theorem, but the proper attribution for the theorem as it is formulated below is to Halpern–Läuchli–Laver–Pincus or HLLP (named after James D. Halpern, Hans Läuchli,
777: 318: 270: 106: 326: 440: 567: 705: 931: 114: 887: 855: 791: 823: 936: 36: 728: 424:{\displaystyle \bigcup _{n\in \omega }\left(\prod _{i<d}S_{i}(n)\right)\subset C_{k}{\text{ for some }}k\leq r.} 272: 278: 230: 66: 551:{\displaystyle S_{\langle T_{i}:i\in d\rangle }^{d}=\bigcup _{n\in \omega }\left(\prod _{i<d}T_{i}(n)\right)} 667:{\displaystyle \mathbb {S} ^{d}=\bigcup _{\langle T_{i}:i\in d\rangle }S_{\langle T_{i}:i\in d\rangle }^{d}.} 926: 217:{\displaystyle \bigcup _{n\in \omega }\left(\prod _{i<d}T_{i}(n)\right)=C_{1}\cup \cdots \cup C_{r},} 681: 707: 28: 896: 864: 832: 800: 910: 878: 846: 814: 906: 874: 842: 810: 40: 901: 869: 853:
Milliken, Keith R. (1981), "A partition theorem for the infinite subtrees of a tree",
805: 920: 837: 45: 20: 32: 885:
Pincus, David; Halpern, James D. (1981), "Partitions of products",
789:
Halpern, James D.; Läuchli, Hans (1966), "A partition theorem",
718:, but that the homogeneous subtree guaranteed by the theorem is 108:
be a sequence of finitely splitting trees of height ω. Let
821:
Milliken, Keith R. (1979), "A Ramsey theorem for trees",
27:
is a partition result about finite products of infinite
16:
Partition result about finite products of infinite trees
678:
The HLLP theorem says that not only is the collection
731: 684: 570: 443: 329: 281: 233: 117: 69: 771: 699: 666: 550: 423: 312: 264: 216: 100: 888:Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 856:Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 792:Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 772:{\displaystyle T=\langle T_{i}:i\in d\rangle .} 31:. Its original purpose was to give a model for 8: 763: 738: 651: 626: 616: 591: 474: 449: 313:{\displaystyle \langle T_{i}:i\in d\rangle } 307: 282: 265:{\displaystyle \langle S_{i}:i\in d\rangle } 259: 234: 101:{\displaystyle \langle T_{i}:i\in d\rangle } 95: 70: 932:Theorems in the foundations of mathematics 900: 868: 836: 804: 745: 730: 691: 687: 686: 683: 655: 633: 625: 598: 590: 577: 573: 572: 569: 528: 512: 491: 478: 456: 448: 442: 404: 398: 371: 355: 334: 328: 289: 280: 241: 232: 227:then there exists a sequence of subtrees 205: 186: 159: 143: 122: 116: 77: 68: 49: 7: 14: 902:10.1090/s0002-9947-1981-0626489-3 870:10.1090/s0002-9947-1981-0590416-8 806:10.1090/s0002-9947-1966-0200172-2 700:{\displaystyle \mathbb {S} ^{d}} 824:Journal of Combinatorial Theory 48:, and David Pincus), following 540: 534: 383: 377: 171: 165: 1: 838:10.1016/0097-3165(79)90101-8 37:Boolean prime ideal theorem 953: 25:Halpern–Läuchli theorem 773: 701: 668: 552: 425: 314: 266: 218: 102: 774: 702: 669: 553: 426: 315: 267: 219: 103: 729: 682: 568: 441: 406: for some  327: 279: 231: 115: 67: 660: 483: 434:Alternatively, let 937:Trees (set theory) 769: 697: 664: 621: 620: 548: 523: 502: 444: 421: 366: 345: 310: 262: 214: 154: 133: 98: 720:strongly embedded 708:partition regular 586: 508: 487: 407: 351: 330: 273:strongly embedded 139: 118: 944: 913: 904: 881: 872: 849: 840: 817: 808: 778: 776: 775: 770: 750: 749: 714: <  706: 704: 703: 698: 696: 695: 690: 673: 671: 670: 665: 659: 654: 638: 637: 619: 603: 602: 582: 581: 576: 557: 555: 554: 549: 547: 543: 533: 532: 522: 501: 482: 477: 461: 460: 430: 428: 427: 422: 408: 405: 403: 402: 390: 386: 376: 375: 365: 344: 319: 317: 316: 311: 294: 293: 271: 269: 268: 263: 246: 245: 223: 221: 220: 215: 210: 209: 191: 190: 178: 174: 164: 163: 153: 132: 107: 105: 104: 99: 82: 81: 39:is true but the 952: 951: 947: 946: 945: 943: 942: 941: 917: 916: 884: 852: 820: 788: 785: 741: 727: 726: 685: 680: 679: 629: 594: 571: 566: 565: 524: 507: 503: 452: 439: 438: 394: 367: 350: 346: 325: 324: 285: 277: 276: 237: 229: 228: 201: 182: 155: 138: 134: 113: 112: 73: 65: 64: 50:Milliken (1979) 41:axiom of choice 17: 12: 11: 5: 950: 948: 940: 939: 934: 929: 919: 918: 915: 914: 895:(2): 549–568, 882: 863:(1): 137–148, 850: 831:(3): 215–237, 818: 784: 781: 780: 779: 768: 765: 762: 759: 756: 753: 748: 744: 740: 737: 734: 694: 689: 676: 675: 663: 658: 653: 650: 647: 644: 641: 636: 632: 628: 624: 618: 615: 612: 609: 606: 601: 597: 593: 589: 585: 580: 575: 559: 558: 546: 542: 539: 536: 531: 527: 521: 518: 515: 511: 506: 500: 497: 494: 490: 486: 481: 476: 473: 470: 467: 464: 459: 455: 451: 447: 432: 431: 420: 417: 414: 411: 401: 397: 393: 389: 385: 382: 379: 374: 370: 364: 361: 358: 354: 349: 343: 340: 337: 333: 309: 306: 303: 300: 297: 292: 288: 284: 261: 258: 255: 252: 249: 244: 240: 236: 225: 224: 213: 208: 204: 200: 197: 194: 189: 185: 181: 177: 173: 170: 167: 162: 158: 152: 149: 146: 142: 137: 131: 128: 125: 121: 97: 94: 91: 88: 85: 80: 76: 72: 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 949: 938: 935: 933: 930: 928: 927:Ramsey theory 925: 924: 922: 912: 908: 903: 898: 894: 890: 889: 883: 880: 876: 871: 866: 862: 858: 857: 851: 848: 844: 839: 834: 830: 826: 825: 819: 816: 812: 807: 802: 798: 794: 793: 787: 786: 782: 766: 760: 757: 754: 751: 746: 742: 735: 732: 725: 724: 723: 721: 717: 713: 709: 692: 661: 656: 648: 645: 642: 639: 634: 630: 622: 613: 610: 607: 604: 599: 595: 587: 583: 578: 564: 563: 562: 544: 537: 529: 525: 519: 516: 513: 509: 504: 498: 495: 492: 488: 484: 479: 471: 468: 465: 462: 457: 453: 445: 437: 436: 435: 418: 415: 412: 409: 399: 395: 391: 387: 380: 372: 368: 362: 359: 356: 352: 347: 341: 338: 335: 331: 323: 322: 321: 304: 301: 298: 295: 290: 286: 274: 256: 253: 250: 247: 242: 238: 211: 206: 202: 198: 195: 192: 187: 183: 179: 175: 168: 160: 156: 150: 147: 144: 140: 135: 129: 126: 123: 119: 111: 110: 109: 92: 89: 86: 83: 78: 74: 62: 58: 53: 51: 47: 46:Richard Laver 42: 38: 35:in which the 34: 30: 26: 22: 892: 886: 860: 854: 828: 827:, Series A, 822: 796: 790: 719: 715: 711: 677: 560: 433: 226: 60: 56: 54: 24: 18: 799:: 360–367, 21:mathematics 921:Categories 783:References 320:such that 33:set theory 764:⟩ 758:∈ 739:⟨ 710:for each 652:⟩ 646:∈ 627:⟨ 617:⟩ 611:∈ 592:⟨ 588:⋃ 510:∏ 499:ω 496:∈ 489:⋃ 475:⟩ 469:∈ 450:⟨ 413:≤ 392:⊂ 353:∏ 342:ω 339:∈ 332:⋃ 308:⟩ 302:∈ 283:⟨ 260:⟩ 254:∈ 235:⟨ 199:∪ 196:⋯ 193:∪ 141:∏ 130:ω 127:∈ 120:⋃ 96:⟩ 90:∈ 71:⟨ 63:< ω, 911:0626489 879:0590416 847:0535155 815:0200172 909:  877:  845:  813:  23:, the 29:trees 561:and 517:< 360:< 148:< 55:Let 897:doi 893:267 865:doi 861:263 833:doi 801:doi 797:124 722:in 275:in 19:In 923:: 907:MR 905:, 891:, 875:MR 873:, 859:, 843:MR 841:, 829:26 811:MR 809:, 795:, 52:. 899:: 867:: 835:: 803:: 767:. 761:d 755:i 752:: 747:i 743:T 736:= 733:T 716:ω 712:d 693:d 688:S 674:. 662:. 657:d 649:d 643:i 640:: 635:i 631:T 623:S 614:d 608:i 605:: 600:i 596:T 584:= 579:d 574:S 545:) 541:) 538:n 535:( 530:i 526:T 520:d 514:i 505:( 493:n 485:= 480:d 472:d 466:i 463:: 458:i 454:T 446:S 419:. 416:r 410:k 400:k 396:C 388:) 384:) 381:n 378:( 373:i 369:S 363:d 357:i 348:( 336:n 305:d 299:i 296:: 291:i 287:T 257:d 251:i 248:: 243:i 239:S 212:, 207:r 203:C 188:1 184:C 180:= 176:) 172:) 169:n 166:( 161:i 157:T 151:d 145:i 136:( 124:n 93:d 87:i 84:: 79:i 75:T 61:r 59:, 57:d

Index

mathematics
trees
set theory
Boolean prime ideal theorem
axiom of choice
Richard Laver
Milliken (1979)
strongly embedded
partition regular
Transactions of the American Mathematical Society
doi
10.1090/s0002-9947-1966-0200172-2
MR
0200172
Journal of Combinatorial Theory
doi
10.1016/0097-3165(79)90101-8
MR
0535155
Transactions of the American Mathematical Society
doi
10.1090/s0002-9947-1981-0590416-8
MR
0590416
Transactions of the American Mathematical Society
doi
10.1090/s0002-9947-1981-0626489-3
MR
0626489
Categories

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.