Knowledge

Performative utterance

Source đź“ť

351:
Skinner 'there is a sense in which we need to understand why a certain proposition has been put forward if we wish to understand the proposition itself'. He values agency over structure and stresses the importance of authorial intentions. Skinner therefore proposes to study historical sources in order to retrieve the convictions the author held, reflect on their coherence and investigate possible motives for the illocutionary act. This practical method seeks to deal with the blurred distinction between text and context and offer a meaningful way of interpreting historical reality.
386:. Additionally, according to Sedgwick, performative utterances can be 'transformative' performatives, which create an instant change of personal or environmental status, or 'promisory' performatives, which describe the world as it might be in the future. These categories are not exclusive, so an utterance may well have both qualities. As Sedgwick observes, performative utterances can be revoked, either by the person who uttered them ("I take back my promise"), or by some other party not immediately involved, like the state (for example, 334:
Performativity has a political aspect that consists in what Derrida has described as the breaking force, by which an utterance changes its context. Butler assigns an important role to what Austin has called infelicities and parasitic uses of language. Quotations, parodies and other deviations from official discourse can become instruments of power that affect society.
284:, it states that neither the meaning, nor the context of a text can be defined in its entirety. Instead of emphasizing linguistic rules, scholars within this strand stress that the performative utterance is intertwined with structures of power. Because a text inevitably changes a situation or discourse, the distinction between text and context is blurred. 187:
conditions have to be met (e.g. a person who pronounces a marriage must be authorized to do so). Besides the context, the performative utterance itself is unambiguous as well. The words of an illocutionary act have to be expressed in earnest; if not, Austin discards them as a parasitic use of language.
302:
holds with Austin and Searle that by illocutionary force, language itself can transform and effect. However, he criticizes the notion of 'felicity conditions' and the idea that the success of a performative utterance is determined by conventions. Derrida values the distinctiveness of every individual
242:
to its broader context, that is to say everything outside the text itself. The question whether a performative is separable from the situation it emerged in is relevant when one addresses for example the status of individual intentions or speech as a resource of power. There are two main theoretical
481:
In 1972 Jacques Derrida published the article 'Signature Événement Contexte', in which he criticises several aspects of Austin's theory on the performative utterance. The first English translation appeared in 1977 in the first volume of Glyph. In the second volume (1977) Searle published an article
350:
Skinner agrees with Derrida that contexts in their entirety are irretrievable but nevertheless states that there is a relevant context outside the text that can be described in a plausible way. Extensive research is required to relate historical texts to their contemporary discourses. According to
199:
tried to develop his own account of speech acts, suggesting that these acts are a form of rule-governed behaviour. On the one hand, Searle discerns rules that merely regulate language, such as referring and predicating. These rules account for the "propositional content" of sentences. On the other
186:
Every performative utterance has its own procedure and risks of failure that Austin calls 'infelicities'. He sees a sharp distinction between the individual text and the 'total speech act situation' surrounding it. According to Austin, in order to successfully perform an illocutionary act, certain
318:
Besides the consequential effects, the dissolution of the text-context divide is also caused by iterability. Due to the possibility of repetition, the intentions of an individual actor can never be fully present in a speech act. The core of a performative utterance is therefore not constituted by
271:
that sees performance as a repeatable ritual. The focus here is largely on individual sentences in the active first person voice, rather than on politics or discourse. The syntactical analyses are firmly anchored in analytical epistemology, as the distinction between the research object and its
333:
Notwithstanding such social restraints, Butler underscores the possibility of agency. The boundaries of a discourse need continuous re-demarcation and this is where speech can escape its constriction. The emphasis on the limits of what is allowed to be said also frames that what is silenced.
346:
developed classical and postmodern theories on performative texts into a concrete research method. Using Austin's vocabulary, he seeks to recover what historical authors were doing in writing their texts, which corresponds with the performance of illocutionary acts. According to Skinner,
243:
strands in research today. One emphasizes the predetermined conventions surrounding a performative utterance and the clear distinction between text and context. Another emphasizes the active construction of reality through spoken and written texts and is related to theories of
203:
This focus on effect implies a conscious actor and Searle assumes that language stems from an intrinsic intentionality of the mind. These intentions set the prerequisites for the performance of speech acts and Searle sets out to map their necessary and sufficient conditions.
168:. When, for instance, one uses the word "Go!" in order to command someone to leave the room then this utterance is part of the performance of a command; and the sentence, according to Austin, is neither true nor false; hence the sentence is a performative; – still, it is 200:
hand, he discerns rules that are constitutive in character and define behaviour (e.g. when making a promise). These rules are the conventions underlying performative utterances and they enable not only representation and expression, but also communication.
314:
According to Derrida, the effects caused by a performative text are in a sense also part of it. In this way, the distinction between a text and that what is outside it dissolves. For this reason it is pointless to try to define the context of a speech act.
266:
Early theories acknowledge that performance and text are both embedded in a system of rules and that the effects they can produce depend on convention and recurrence. In this sense, text is an instance of 'restored behaviour', a term introduced by
219:, if "the successful performance of the speech act is sufficient to bring about the fit between words and world, to make the propositional content true." Searle believes that this double direction of fit contrasts the simple word-to-world fit of 307:, because it has a specific effect in the particular situation in which it is performed. It is because of this effect or 'breaking force' that Derrida calls the possibility of repeating a text 'iterability', a word derived from Latin 70:
philosophical claim that the utterances always "describe" or "constate" something and are thus always true or false. After mentioning several examples of sentences which are not so used, and not truth-evaluable (among them
362:
and Robert Harnish claimed that performatives are successful only if recipients infer the intention behind the literal meaning, and that therefore the success of the performative act is determined by the receiving side.
414:). Such a writing form is claimed to be, in itself, a form of performance. It is said to more accurately reflect the fleeting and ephemeral nature of a performance, and the various tricks of memory and 326:
offers a political interpretation of the concept of the performative utterance. Power in the form of active censorship defines and regulates the domain of a certain discourse. Indebted to the work of
347:
philosophical ideas are intertwined with claims of power. Every text is an act of communication that positions itself in relation to the status quo it seeks to change.
614: 482:
called: 'Reiterating the differences: a reply to Derrida', in which he defended Austin's theories. Derrida responded with the essay 'Limited Inc a b c...', (1977).
1435: 734: 1208: 164:; to utter an "explicit" performative sentence is to make explicit what act one is performing. However, there are also "implicit", "primitive", or 287:
Austin and Searle thought in terms of demarcated contexts and transparent intentions, two issues that in the 1970s led Searle into polemics with
1076: 743: 280:
The second set of theories on performance and text diverged from the tradition represented by Austin and Searle. Bearing the stamp of
122:), the performance of which, again, would not normally be described as simply "saying" or "describing" something (cf. Austin 1962, 5). 118:
The uttering of a performative is, or is part of, the doing of a certain kind of action (Austin later deals with them under the name
516: 1430: 1163: 817: 1284: 1158: 727: 179:
As Austin observes, the acts purported to be performed by performative utterances may be socially contested. For instance,
936: 757: 103:
true or false; and he calls such sentences "constatives". In contrast to them, Austin defines "performatives" as follows:
225: 211:
that performatives are true or false just like constatives. Searle further claimed that performatives are what he calls
822: 58: 330:, Butler expounds how subjects are produced by their context, because the possibilities of speech are predetermined. 910: 1304: 966: 787: 95:
In order to define performatives, Austin refers to those sentences which conform to the old prejudice in that they
238:
Building on the notion of performative utterances, scholars have theorized on the relation of a spoken or written
1309: 1259: 1021: 720: 115:; instead when something is wrong with them then they are "unhappy", while if nothing is wrong they are "happy". 1369: 1228: 807: 165: 1364: 905: 158: 1394: 1031: 1006: 946: 845: 777: 379: 239: 50: 38: 1289: 1183: 1148: 1036: 1011: 855: 772: 157:
As Austin later notices himself, these examples belong (more or less strikingly) to what Austin calls,
403: 1274: 1081: 860: 399: 415: 1425: 1359: 1324: 1269: 1213: 1116: 1101: 1071: 1051: 1026: 895: 880: 657: 432: 1404: 1329: 1299: 1264: 1244: 1173: 1153: 1091: 1086: 996: 986: 971: 915: 666: 215:; this is a technical notion of Searle's account: according to his conception, an utterance is a 176:
performative, for it does not make explicit that the act the speaker is performing is a command.
53:
which not only describe a given reality, but also change the social reality they are describing.
42: 220: 140:
take this woman to be my lawful wedded wife)" – as uttered in the course of a marriage ceremony.
1384: 1339: 1319: 1279: 1218: 1188: 1168: 961: 890: 512: 452: 268: 252: 119: 84: 1389: 1314: 1203: 981: 319:
animating intentions, as Austin and Searle would have it, but by the structure of language.
180: 1193: 1096: 991: 956: 411: 343: 327: 299: 292: 263:, proving their methodological use for example in the interpretation of historical texts. 256: 1379: 1374: 1294: 1178: 1056: 951: 792: 462: 31: 712: 1419: 1066: 1041: 875: 447: 323: 281: 112: 76: 1334: 1254: 1121: 1001: 885: 865: 702: 437: 427: 387: 371: 244: 63: 655:
Bach, Kent; Harnish, Robert (August 1981). "Linguistic Communication and Speech".
17: 1249: 1223: 1106: 870: 797: 442: 407: 196: 72: 1399: 1046: 812: 767: 762: 457: 304: 288: 260: 80: 67: 707: 1198: 1016: 941: 920: 850: 802: 782: 359: 248: 30:
For the broader philosophical and critical applications of the concept, see
402:; they are used as a justification for an attempt to create a new form of 1111: 900: 418:
that happen in the mind of the viewer during and after the performance.
670: 83:
and "ethical" propositions), he introduces "performative" sentences or
644:. Vol. 1 regarding method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 183:, may be accepted to constitute a divorce by some, but not by others. 383: 150:"I give and bequeath my watch to my brother" – as occurring in a will 976: 108: 375: 716: 251:. The ideas about performance and text have contributed to the 136: 153:"I bet you sixpence it will rain tomorrow" (Austin 1962, 5) 374:
argued that there are performative aspects to nearly all
99:
used to describe or constate something, and which thus
181:"I divorce you", said three times by a man to his wife 590:
Derrida, Jacques (1988). "Signature Event Context".
1352: 1237: 1141: 1134: 929: 838: 831: 750: 535:
Speech Acts, an essay in the philosophy of language
195:Building on Austin's thought, language philosopher 555:Intentionality, an essay in the philosophy of mind 1209:Segmented discourse representation theory (SDRT) 615:Excitable speech: A politics of the performative 27:Category of utterances in philosophy of language 635: 633: 631: 629: 627: 625: 585: 583: 581: 579: 728: 607: 605: 603: 601: 572:. New York: Taylor & Francis. p. 36. 548: 546: 544: 528: 526: 524: 503: 501: 499: 56:In a 1955 lecture series, later published as 8: 367:Performativeness as non-dichotomous variable 1138: 835: 735: 721: 713: 272:context is not conceived as problematic. 557:. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 537:. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 495: 474: 1164:Discourse representation theory (DRT) 7: 570:Performance Studies, an Introduction 1436:Formal semantics (natural language) 1077:Quantificational variability effect 744:Formal semantics (natural language) 207:Searle argued in his 1989 article 25: 398:The above ideas have influenced 107:Performative utterances are not 511:Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962. 1159:Combinatory categorial grammar 1: 937:Antecedent-contained deletion 703:'Performative' on Glottopedia 568:Schechner, Richard (2006). 509:How to Do Things with Words 298:The postmodern philosopher 59:How to Do Things with Words 1452: 818:Syntax–semantics interface 166:"inexplicit" performatives 90: 29: 1310:Question under discussion 1260:Conversational scoreboard 1037:Intersective modification 1022:Homogeneity (linguistics) 640:Skinner, Quentin (2003). 1370:Distributional semantics 688:. Duke University Press. 553:Searle, John R. (1983). 533:Searle, John R. (1974). 390:vows pre-legalisation). 130:Austin gives are these: 126:The initial examples of 1365:Computational semantics 1102:Subsective modification 906:Propositional attitudes 612:Butler, Judith (1997). 47:performative utterances 1431:Philosophy of language 1395:Philosophy of language 1032:Inalienable possession 1012:Free choice inferences 1007:Faultless disagreement 778:Generalized quantifier 684:Sedgwick, Eve (2003). 618:. New York: Routledge. 338:Historical methodology 276:Postmodernist theories 209:How Performatives Work 143:"I name this ship the 128:performative sentences 39:philosophy of language 1290:Plural quantification 1184:Inquisitive semantics 1149:Alternative semantics 87:as another instance. 1275:Function application 1082:Responsive predicate 1072:Privative adjectives 400:performative writing 394:Performative writing 1360:Cognitive semantics 1325:Strawson entailment 1270:Existential closure 1214:Situation semantics 1117:Temperature paradox 1087:Rising declaratives 1052:Modal subordination 1027:Hurford disjunction 987:Discourse relations 658:Language in Society 642:Visions of Politics 433:Illocutionary force 91:Austin's definition 1405:Semantics of logic 1330:Strict conditional 1300:Quantifier raising 1265:Downward entailing 1245:Autonomy of syntax 1174:Generative grammar 1154:Categorial grammar 1092:Scalar implicature 997:Epistemic modality 972:De dicto and de re 355:The receiving side 120:illocutionary acts 43:speech acts theory 1413: 1412: 1385:Logic translation 1348: 1347: 1340:Universal grinder 1320:Squiggle operator 1280:Meaning postulate 1219:Supervaluationism 1189:Intensional logic 1169:Dynamic semantics 1130: 1129: 962:Crossover effects 911:Tense–aspect–mood 891:Lexical semantics 453:Performative turn 269:Richard Schechner 253:performative turn 234:Performative text 85:illocutionary act 66:argued against a 18:Performative text 16:(Redirected from 1443: 1390:Linguistics wars 1315:Semantic parsing 1204:Montague grammar 1139: 982:Deontic modality 836: 823:Truth conditions 758:Compositionality 751:Central concepts 737: 730: 723: 714: 690: 689: 686:Touching Feeling 681: 675: 674: 652: 646: 645: 637: 620: 619: 609: 596: 595: 587: 574: 573: 565: 559: 558: 550: 539: 538: 530: 519: 505: 483: 479: 404:critical writing 322:The philosopher 229: 21: 1451: 1450: 1446: 1445: 1444: 1442: 1441: 1440: 1416: 1415: 1414: 1409: 1344: 1233: 1194:Lambda calculus 1126: 1097:Sloppy identity 1057:Opaque contexts 992:Donkey anaphora 957:Counterfactuals 925: 827: 746: 741: 708:Dinosaur Comics 699: 694: 693: 683: 682: 678: 654: 653: 649: 639: 638: 623: 611: 610: 599: 589: 588: 577: 567: 566: 562: 552: 551: 542: 532: 531: 522: 506: 497: 492: 487: 486: 480: 476: 471: 424: 412:performance art 396: 369: 357: 344:Quentin Skinner 340: 328:Michel Foucault 300:Jacques Derrida 293:Jacques Derrida 278: 257:social sciences 236: 223: 193: 145:Queen Elizabeth 113:truth-evaluable 111:, that is, not 93: 35: 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 1449: 1447: 1439: 1438: 1433: 1428: 1418: 1417: 1411: 1410: 1408: 1407: 1402: 1397: 1392: 1387: 1382: 1380:Inferentialism 1377: 1375:Formal grammar 1372: 1367: 1362: 1356: 1354: 1350: 1349: 1346: 1345: 1343: 1342: 1337: 1332: 1327: 1322: 1317: 1312: 1307: 1302: 1297: 1295:Possible world 1292: 1287: 1282: 1277: 1272: 1267: 1262: 1257: 1252: 1247: 1241: 1239: 1235: 1234: 1232: 1231: 1226: 1221: 1216: 1211: 1206: 1201: 1196: 1191: 1186: 1181: 1179:Glue semantics 1176: 1171: 1166: 1161: 1156: 1151: 1145: 1143: 1142:Formal systems 1136: 1132: 1131: 1128: 1127: 1125: 1124: 1119: 1114: 1109: 1104: 1099: 1094: 1089: 1084: 1079: 1074: 1069: 1067:Polarity items 1064: 1059: 1054: 1049: 1044: 1039: 1034: 1029: 1024: 1019: 1014: 1009: 1004: 999: 994: 989: 984: 979: 974: 969: 964: 959: 954: 952:Conservativity 949: 944: 939: 933: 931: 927: 926: 924: 923: 918: 916:Quantification 913: 908: 903: 898: 893: 888: 883: 878: 873: 868: 863: 858: 853: 848: 842: 840: 833: 829: 828: 826: 825: 820: 815: 810: 805: 800: 795: 793:Presupposition 790: 785: 780: 775: 770: 765: 760: 754: 752: 748: 747: 742: 740: 739: 732: 725: 717: 711: 710: 705: 698: 697:External links 695: 692: 691: 676: 665:(2): 270–274. 647: 621: 597: 575: 560: 540: 520: 494: 493: 491: 488: 485: 484: 473: 472: 470: 467: 466: 465: 463:Performativity 460: 455: 450: 445: 440: 435: 430: 423: 420: 416:referentiality 395: 392: 368: 365: 356: 353: 342:The historian 339: 336: 277: 274: 235: 232: 192: 189: 155: 154: 151: 148: 141: 124: 123: 116: 92: 89: 77:interrogatives 32:Performativity 26: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1448: 1437: 1434: 1432: 1429: 1427: 1424: 1423: 1421: 1406: 1403: 1401: 1398: 1396: 1393: 1391: 1388: 1386: 1383: 1381: 1378: 1376: 1373: 1371: 1368: 1366: 1363: 1361: 1358: 1357: 1355: 1351: 1341: 1338: 1336: 1333: 1331: 1328: 1326: 1323: 1321: 1318: 1316: 1313: 1311: 1308: 1306: 1303: 1301: 1298: 1296: 1293: 1291: 1288: 1286: 1283: 1281: 1278: 1276: 1273: 1271: 1268: 1266: 1263: 1261: 1258: 1256: 1253: 1251: 1248: 1246: 1243: 1242: 1240: 1236: 1230: 1227: 1225: 1222: 1220: 1217: 1215: 1212: 1210: 1207: 1205: 1202: 1200: 1197: 1195: 1192: 1190: 1187: 1185: 1182: 1180: 1177: 1175: 1172: 1170: 1167: 1165: 1162: 1160: 1157: 1155: 1152: 1150: 1147: 1146: 1144: 1140: 1137: 1133: 1123: 1120: 1118: 1115: 1113: 1110: 1108: 1105: 1103: 1100: 1098: 1095: 1093: 1090: 1088: 1085: 1083: 1080: 1078: 1075: 1073: 1070: 1068: 1065: 1063: 1062:Performatives 1060: 1058: 1055: 1053: 1050: 1048: 1045: 1043: 1042:Logophoricity 1040: 1038: 1035: 1033: 1030: 1028: 1025: 1023: 1020: 1018: 1015: 1013: 1010: 1008: 1005: 1003: 1000: 998: 995: 993: 990: 988: 985: 983: 980: 978: 975: 973: 970: 968: 965: 963: 960: 958: 955: 953: 950: 948: 945: 943: 940: 938: 935: 934: 932: 928: 922: 919: 917: 914: 912: 909: 907: 904: 902: 899: 897: 894: 892: 889: 887: 884: 882: 879: 877: 876:Evidentiality 874: 872: 869: 867: 864: 862: 859: 857: 854: 852: 849: 847: 844: 843: 841: 837: 834: 830: 824: 821: 819: 816: 814: 811: 809: 806: 804: 801: 799: 796: 794: 791: 789: 786: 784: 781: 779: 776: 774: 771: 769: 766: 764: 761: 759: 756: 755: 753: 749: 745: 738: 733: 731: 726: 724: 719: 718: 715: 709: 706: 704: 701: 700: 696: 687: 680: 677: 672: 668: 664: 660: 659: 651: 648: 643: 636: 634: 632: 630: 628: 626: 622: 617: 616: 608: 606: 604: 602: 598: 593: 586: 584: 582: 580: 576: 571: 564: 561: 556: 549: 547: 545: 541: 536: 529: 527: 525: 521: 518: 517:0-19-824553-X 514: 510: 507:Austin, J.L. 504: 502: 500: 496: 489: 478: 475: 468: 464: 461: 459: 456: 454: 451: 449: 448:Judith Butler 446: 444: 441: 439: 436: 434: 431: 429: 426: 425: 421: 419: 417: 413: 410:(often about 409: 405: 401: 393: 391: 389: 385: 381: 377: 373: 366: 364: 361: 354: 352: 348: 345: 337: 335: 331: 329: 325: 324:Judith Butler 320: 316: 312: 311:, to repeat. 310: 306: 301: 296: 294: 290: 285: 283: 282:postmodernism 275: 273: 270: 264: 262: 258: 254: 250: 246: 241: 233: 231: 227: 222: 218: 214: 210: 205: 201: 198: 190: 188: 184: 182: 177: 175: 171: 167: 163: 162:performatives 161: 152: 149: 146: 142: 139: 138: 133: 132: 131: 129: 121: 117: 114: 110: 109:true or false 106: 105: 104: 102: 98: 88: 86: 82: 78: 74: 69: 65: 61: 60: 54: 52: 48: 44: 40: 33: 19: 1335:Type shifter 1305:Quantization 1255:Continuation 1122:Veridicality 1061: 1002:Exhaustivity 967:Cumulativity 886:Indexicality 866:Definiteness 861:Conditionals 788:Logical form 685: 679: 662: 656: 650: 641: 613: 591: 569: 563: 554: 534: 508: 477: 438:J. L. Austin 428:Eve Sedgwick 397: 388:gay marriage 372:Eve Sedgwick 370: 358: 349: 341: 332: 321: 317: 313: 308: 297: 286: 279: 265: 245:human agency 237: 216: 213:declarations 212: 208: 206: 202: 194: 185: 178: 173: 169: 159: 156: 144: 135: 127: 125: 100: 96: 94: 64:J. L. Austin 57: 55: 46: 36: 1250:Context set 1224:Type theory 1107:Subtrigging 871:Disjunction 798:Proposition 592:Limited Inc 443:John Searle 408:performance 224: [ 217:declaration 197:John Searle 191:John Searle 75:sentences, 73:nonsensical 1426:Pragmatics 1420:Categories 1400:Pragmatics 1047:Mirativity 813:Speech act 768:Entailment 763:Denotation 490:References 458:Pragmatics 305:speech act 289:postmodern 261:humanities 221:assertives 81:directives 68:positivist 1199:Mereology 1135:Formalism 1017:Givenness 942:Cataphora 930:Phenomena 921:Vagueness 851:Ambiguity 803:Reference 783:Intension 773:Extension 380:sentences 360:Kent Bach 249:discourse 51:sentences 1353:See also 1238:Concepts 1112:Telicity 947:Coercion 901:Negation 896:Modality 846:Anaphora 422:See also 291:thinker 174:explicit 160:explicit 856:Binding 671:4167219 594:: 1–23. 384:phrases 309:iterare 255:in the 134:"I do ( 37:In the 1285:Monads 832:Topics 669:  515:  406:about 382:, and 977:De se 881:Focus 839:Areas 808:Scope 667:JSTOR 469:Notes 376:words 228:] 513:ISBN 259:and 247:and 240:text 49:are 41:and 1229:TTR 172:an 170:not 137:sc. 101:are 97:are 1422:: 663:10 661:. 624:^ 600:^ 578:^ 543:^ 523:^ 498:^ 378:, 295:. 230:. 226:de 79:, 62:, 45:, 736:e 729:t 722:v 673:. 147:" 34:. 20:)

Index

Performative text
Performativity
philosophy of language
speech acts theory
sentences
How to Do Things with Words
J. L. Austin
positivist
nonsensical
interrogatives
directives
illocutionary act
true or false
truth-evaluable
illocutionary acts
sc.
explicit performatives
"inexplicit" performatives
"I divorce you", said three times by a man to his wife
John Searle
assertives
de
text
human agency
discourse
performative turn
social sciences
humanities
Richard Schechner
postmodernism

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑