Knowledge (XXG)

Time and Eternity (philosophy book)

Source 📝

301:; he asks how concepts can be applied to that which is above all concepts and finds that all propositions about God are symbolical. He defines religious and non-religious symbolism as differing in two respects. Firstly, religious symbols cannot be translated into logical propositions because they refer to an (ineffable) experience rather than a proposition. Secondly, the relationship between the religious symbol and what is symbolised is one of evocation rather than "meaning", as meaning is a concept, which is absent in the mystical experience. "Yet in some way this symbolic language evokes in us some glimpse, some hint, seen dimly through the mists and fogs which envelop us, of that being who stands above all human thought and conception." He goes on to write that some of these symbols feel more appropriate than others (e.g. God is love not hate). 361:. He writes that proofs and disproofs for God are equally false, as God is only accessible by intuition and not logic. "… the production by philosophers of proofs of the unreality of space, time, and the temporal world generally, is a direct result of their mistaking of their mystical propositions for factual propositions." Further, proofs of God actually harm religion as they make him a part of the natural order - a point on which he says that he agrees with Kant. Conversely acosmism (the denial of the reality of the world) has its root in the mystical moment, within which there is no other truth, God is the supreme reality and there is no naturalistic world. However, this is a symbolic truth, rather than a statement of fact. Its counterpart in naturalism is atheism, which denies the reality of God. 367:"The pure religious consciousness lies in a region which is forever beyond all proof or disproof. This is a necessary consequence of the "utterly other" character of God from the world, and of the "utterly other" character of the world from God. The eternal order is not the natural order, and the natural order is not the eternal order. The two orders intersect, but in the intersection each remains what it is. Each is wholly self-contained. Therefore, it is impossible to pass, by any logical inference, from one to the other. This at once precludes as impossible any talk either of the proof or disproof of religion." 502:, but no more successful. For Friedman, the philosophy that Stace lays out in the book is derived from metaphysical speculation (that, like the ideas of Huxley and Coomaraswamy, is influenced by Vedanta), rather than mystical experience. Central to Friedman's critique is the notion that there is a vast gulf between the mystical experience which Stace defines as beyond thought, and his philosophical system built on this. He also mentions that mystics do not always agree on what experiences, symbols and philosophies are the closest to the divine. 460:
religious intuition that would be of particular interest to students of “Oriental and comparative philosophy”. The central idea upon which Stace's thought stands or falls, for Kaplan, is that religious language is evocative rather than descriptive. In this both religionists and naturalists will find problems. For the former, Stace can only account for the appropriateness of religious language by relying on ‘nearness’ to the divine rather than on resemblance, and this relies on ‘a vague panpsychism’ and levels of being in the manner of
428:, also by Stace and published in 1952. He points out that all three books mark a new direction for Stace who was previously best known as an empiricist and naturalist. For Aldrich this new intellectual interest results in a sharp dualism in both Stace’s personality and his thought. However, he writes that fortunately Stace’s philosophical background prevents him from supposing that scientific empiricism can confirm religious experience, indeed his religious philosophy is the sort “that a 397: 440:
eternity are utterly unrelated as Stace maintains. He identifies points in Stace's thought where there is continuity between these two states and mystical language does appear to refer to concepts. Finally he rejects the book's analogy of mystical experience to the evocative power of art, maintaining that art must be somewhat related to logic. Nonetheless, Bixler does concur that the book is a fascinating confessio fidei and personal statement. A year later, he reviewed
433:
religious language is evocative of the mystical experience is problematic, because it is difficult to determine what language is adequate without resorting to literal or abstract ideas. Rudolf Otto's notion of analogy, rejected by Stace, is more robust. Aldrich points out a contradiction in Stace's reliance on hierarchies of being and values to more adequately refer to God, as this implies continuity between the world and eternity, which Stace denies.
274:- the characterisation of God as void, silence or non-being - which Stace maintains is an idea found in all religions. He maintains that mystical experience is shared by all mankind, it is only the theories about it that differ. On this point he says he is in agreement with Otto. In this experience the distinction between subject and object is overcome, indeed there is no difference between the experiencer and the experience. 294:, because no words or concepts can be applied to God who is without qualities or predicates. Thus, God cannot be comprehended by the intellect, but is apprehended by intuition. "... it is of the very nature of intellect to involve the subject-object opposition. But in the mystic experience this opposition is transcended. Therefore the intellect is incapable of understanding it. Therefore it is incomprehensible, ineffable." 305: 343:"What is the meaning of the metaphor of intersection? This intersection means precisely what the eternal moment is experienced to be. It is one and the same human consciousness which experiences both the temporal or natural world and that eternal and infinite order which is disclosed in mystical illumination." 280:"It is not that the mystic has an experience, even a direct vision, of God. For in that case God would be the object for the soul as subject. The distinction between God and the soul, as object and subject respectively, is wholly done away with. The soul passes into the being of God, becomes God, is God." 432:
or a Kant can consort with.” Aldrich argues that Stace's intellectual sophistication is most evident in his ideas about the negative divine, but his thought is liable to all the standard objections where he proposes notions of the positive divine and religious intuition. Specifically, the notion that
439:
reviewed the book twice, in 1952 and 1953. In his first review he wrote that he believed Stace was trying to have his cake and eat it with regards to the truth of both naturalism and mysticism. Bixler also wonders whether the revelation of God can really be free of concepts and thus whether time and
312:
Next Stace explains that there are two orders of being: time (or the world) and eternity (or God), and these intersect in the moment of mystic illumination. He maintains these orders are distinct, so one order cannot dictate to the other. Here he says that he agrees with Kant, who made a distinction
482:
found issue with the notion that the mystical experience is the point of intersection between the temporal and eternal orders. She writes that there are difficulties in Stace defining these orders as two distinct “orders of being”, rather than just as a way of speaking, because this then means some
459:
who believed the book was one of the best on the subject for many many years. He pointed out that the book's distinction between the orders of time and eternity owed much to Kant (which Stace himself acknowledged). Kaplan reflected that it was the book's emphasis placed on mysticism and a universal
336:
Stace next looks at religion’s claims to truth. He draws an analogy between mystical illumination and aesthetic truth, as the truths of both rest on revelation rather than reason. "Either you directly perceive beauty, or you do not. And either you directly perceive God in intuition, or you do not."
257:
The book begins by looking at religion, specifically God as non-being and as being, put by Stace as the negative and positive divine. Stace then defines two orders of being - time and eternity, which he says intersect in the moment of mystic illumination. He goes on to say that the nature of God or
467:
Also noting the unachievable ambition of solving the conflict between naturalism and religion, Martin A Greenman, remarks that one must come to the book “with a certain mood”. Too critical a mood would blind the reader to its religious insights, while the sensitivity and depth of its philosophic
324:
Looking at symbolism in religion, Stace states that there are two types of predicates applied to God: first, the ethically-neutral sort, such as God being mind, power or personhood. Secondly, the ethical kind, where he is love, mercy, or righteousness. He explains that the former qualities are
483:
statements about the temporal order are relevant to what is said about the eternal order and vice versa. Indeed, the interrelation between these two orders is difficult to maintain. She also questioned Stace's characterisation of mystical consciousness as being the same everywhere.
329:, and the latter to a hierarchy of value. In both cases the more adequate symbol are those that are higher in each hierarchy. In rooting symbolism in hierarchies, Stace explicitly states he is in opposition to Otto who thought religious symbolism was based on analogy between the 393:) will always contain contradictions. Known as the doctrine of the Mystery of God, he maintains this is because the intellect is inherently incapable of understanding the Ultimate. All attempts to state the nature of the ultimate necessarily produce contradictions. 42: 464:. While for the naturalist, Stace's system of religious symbolism is doomed to remain mysterious, because it does not allow religious metaphors to be translated literally and neither can it be said how they evoke the experience to which they refer. 478:: “My propositions are elucidatory in this way: he who understands me finally recognizes them as senseless, when he has climbed out through them, on them, over them….He must surmount these propositions: then he sees the world rightly” (6. 54.) 448:. As well as reiterating the points he had made earlier, Bixler judges the second book more favourably and recommends reading the two together to better understand the problems they address. 520:, Tim Bayne says the book contains a “classic” discussion of ineffability. American writer Arthur Goldwag has said that the phrase "that than which there is no other" that he encountered in 408:
agrees with the Upanishad: 'The Father incomprehensible, the Son incomprehensible, the Holy Ghost incomprehensible. . . . Yet not three incomprehensiblies, but one incomprehensible.'"
468:
insights would be lost if one were to approach it in a too enthusiastically religious mood. Greenman finishes by justifying Stace's philosophy to logical positivists by quoting from
687: 337:
Further, he maintains the arguments of both mystics and naturalists in denying each other's positions are invalid, as they concern different realities.
308:"Thus when Plotinus speaks of "the flight of the alone to the Alone,"... evoke in us a measure of the same experience which the author of them had." 738: 377:
In the final chapter Stace looks at mysticism and logic. He returns to the idea that theology and mystical philosophies (he gives the examples of
894: 254:. He says he was motivated to write the book in an attempt to add to the "other half of the truth which I now think naturalism misses". 834: 812: 783: 242:. He explains that the basic idea set out in the book is that all religious thought is symbolic, and that his influences include 889: 486:
More recently, Maurice Friedman writes about the book in the context of the various attempts to find a universal essence - or
473: 121: 386: 17: 143: 544: 200: 93: 669: 516: 238:
is an attempt to set out the fundamental nature of religion, and to deal with the conflict between religion and
884: 723: 705: 401: 258:
eternity is such that all religious language is symbolic and that it is necessarily subject to contradictions.
825: 799: 794: 506: 405: 239: 771: 267: 220: 78: 266:
The first chapter asks what religion is, stating that religious thought is contradictory, is rooted in
756: 487: 212: 208: 204: 193: 52: 499: 469: 396: 298: 751: 326: 271: 846: 830: 808: 779: 128: 116: 41: 869: 700: 682: 479: 461: 436: 354: 154: 864: 718: 664: 456: 417: 382: 513:“the most sophisticated treatment of eternity and time in our century so far”. In his 878: 495: 390: 270:, and that God is fundamentally a mystery. The second and third chapters look at the 251: 228: 291: 290:
Stace then goes on to explain that all religions say that religious revelation is
243: 404:
says flatly that Brahman "is incomprehensible, for it cannot be comprehended".
804: 775: 429: 314: 227:, after writing throughout most of the 1930s and 1940s that was influenced by 196: 74: 224: 82: 524:
was one of a number of factors that contributed to him giving up praying.
358: 330: 318: 70: 135: 378: 321:, although he is critical of Kant’s disregard for mystical experience. 304: 207:. At the time of writing, Stace was a professor of philosophy at 211:, where he had worked since 1932 after a 22-year career in the 129: 494:
is a more systematic attempt at this than those proposed by
363: 339: 276: 189:
Time and Eternity - An Essay on the Philosophy of Religion
155: 34:
Time and Eternity: An Essay in the Philosophy of Religion
18:
Time and Eternity: an Essay in the Philosophy of Religion
451:
Stace was praised for his clarity and ambitious aims in
505:
The book has received more positive support however.
353:
These separate spheres lead Stace to reflect on both
175: 165: 153: 141: 127: 115: 107: 99: 88: 66: 58: 48: 772:A Heart of Wisdom: Religion and Human Wholeness 8: 736:Greenman, Martin A. (Mar. 1953). "Reviews", 32: 333:and qualities found in the natural world. 203:, 169 pp) is a philosophy book written by 40: 31: 739:Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 395: 303: 532: 234:In his introduction Stace writes that 219:was one of his first books about the 7: 845:Goldwag, Arthur (October 9, 2009) 826:Thought: A Very Short Introduction 170:Religion and the Modern Mind  25: 829:Oxford University Press. p. 121. 688:The Journal of Bible and Religion 667:(Jan. 21, 1954). "Book Reviews", 490:- within religion. He finds that 703:(Jul 1953). "Reviews of Books", 685:(Oct., 1952). "Book Reviews", 180:Teachings of the Mystics  1: 851:. Killing the Buddha magazine 895:Philosophy of religion books 848:Confession: Why I Don't Pray 721:(Oct 1953). "Book Reviews", 446:Religion and the Modern Mind 422:Religion and the Modern Mind 420:reviewed the book alongside 325:justified by an appeal to a 27:Book by Walter Terence Stace 406:The creed of St. Athanasius 911: 769:Friedman, Maurice. (2012) 545:Princeton University Press 201:Princeton University Press 94:Princeton University Press 754:(Jan 1954). "New Books", 670:The Journal of Philosophy 517:A Very Short Introduction 39: 800:Eternity and Time's Flow 795:Neville, Robert Cummings 724:Philosophy East and West 706:The Philosophical Review 297:Stace then looks at the 248:Mysticism East and West 890:1952 non-fiction books 727:, 3(3), 1953, 275-276. 691:, 20(4), 272-274, OUP. 409: 309: 221:philosophy of religion 79:Philosophy of Religion 637:Stace (1952) P. 147-8 601:Stace (1952) P. 94-95 399: 313:between the world of 307: 823:Bayne, Tim. (2013). 539:Stace, W. T. (1952) 488:perennial philosophy 437:Julius Seelye Bixler 213:Ceylon Civil Service 209:Princeton University 205:Walter Terence Stace 53:Walter Terence Stace 646:Stace (1952) P. 136 628:Stace (1952) P. 134 610:Stace (1952) P. 142 592:Stace (1952) P. 148 500:Ananda Coomaraswamy 426:The Gate of Silence 36: 752:Emmet, Dorothy, M. 665:Aldrich, Virgil C. 655:Stace (1952) P. 37 619:Stace (1952) P. 82 583:Stace (1952) P. 91 574:Stace (1952) P. 51 565:Stace (1952) P. 40 556:Stace (1952) P. 23 410: 327:hierarchy of being 310: 865:Time and Eternity 709:, 62(3), 479-480. 541:Time and Eternity 522:Time and Eternity 511:Time and Eternity 492:Time and Eternity 453:Time and Eternity 442:Time and Eternity 413:Critical response 375: 374: 351: 350: 288: 287: 246:, especially his 236:Time and Eternity 217:Time and Eternity 185: 184: 100:Publication place 16:(Redirected from 902: 870:Internet Archive 852: 843: 837: 821: 815: 792: 786: 767: 761: 760:, 29(108), 77-78 749: 743: 742:,13(3), 416-417. 734: 728: 716: 710: 698: 692: 680: 674: 662: 656: 653: 647: 644: 638: 635: 629: 626: 620: 617: 611: 608: 602: 599: 593: 590: 584: 581: 575: 572: 566: 563: 557: 554: 548: 537: 507:Robert C Neville 480:Dorothy M. Emmet 462:Samuel Alexander 418:Virgil C Aldrich 364: 340: 277: 176:Followed by 166:Preceded by 157: 131: 44: 37: 21: 910: 909: 905: 904: 903: 901: 900: 899: 885:Mysticism texts 875: 874: 860: 855: 844: 840: 822: 818: 807:. pp. 236-237. 793: 789: 768: 764: 750: 746: 735: 731: 719:Kaplan, Abraham 717: 713: 699: 695: 681: 677: 663: 659: 654: 650: 645: 641: 636: 632: 627: 623: 618: 614: 609: 605: 600: 596: 591: 587: 582: 578: 573: 569: 564: 560: 555: 551: 538: 534: 530: 415: 299:positive divine 272:negative divine 264: 146: 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 908: 906: 898: 897: 892: 887: 877: 876: 873: 872: 859: 858:External links 856: 854: 853: 838: 816: 787: 778:. pp. 98-100. 762: 744: 729: 711: 693: 675: 673:, 51(2), 75-77 657: 648: 639: 630: 621: 612: 603: 594: 585: 576: 567: 558: 549: 531: 529: 526: 457:Abraham Kaplan 414: 411: 373: 372: 369: 368: 355:proofs for God 349: 348: 345: 344: 286: 285: 282: 281: 263: 260: 183: 182: 177: 173: 172: 167: 163: 162: 159: 151: 150: 147: 142: 139: 138: 133: 125: 124: 119: 113: 112: 109: 105: 104: 101: 97: 96: 90: 86: 85: 68: 64: 63: 60: 56: 55: 50: 46: 45: 26: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 907: 896: 893: 891: 888: 886: 883: 882: 880: 871: 867: 866: 862: 861: 857: 850: 849: 842: 839: 836: 835:9780199601721 832: 828: 827: 820: 817: 814: 813:9780791415993 810: 806: 802: 801: 796: 791: 788: 785: 784:9781438403366 781: 777: 774: 773: 766: 763: 759: 758: 753: 748: 745: 741: 740: 733: 730: 726: 725: 720: 715: 712: 708: 707: 702: 697: 694: 690: 689: 684: 679: 676: 672: 671: 666: 661: 658: 652: 649: 643: 640: 634: 631: 625: 622: 616: 613: 607: 604: 598: 595: 589: 586: 580: 577: 571: 568: 562: 559: 553: 550: 546: 542: 536: 533: 527: 525: 523: 519: 518: 512: 508: 503: 501: 497: 496:Aldous Huxley 493: 489: 484: 481: 477: 476: 471: 465: 463: 458: 454: 449: 447: 443: 438: 434: 431: 427: 423: 419: 412: 407: 403: 402:The Upanishad 398: 394: 392: 388: 384: 380: 371: 370: 366: 365: 362: 360: 356: 347: 346: 342: 341: 338: 334: 332: 328: 322: 320: 316: 306: 302: 300: 295: 293: 284: 283: 279: 278: 275: 273: 269: 261: 259: 255: 253: 252:Immanuel Kant 249: 245: 241: 237: 232: 230: 229:phenomenalist 226: 222: 218: 214: 210: 206: 202: 198: 195: 191: 190: 181: 178: 174: 171: 168: 164: 160: 158: 156:LC Class 152: 148: 145: 144:Dewey Decimal 140: 137: 134: 132: 126: 123: 120: 118: 114: 110: 106: 103:United States 102: 98: 95: 91: 87: 84: 80: 76: 72: 69: 65: 61: 57: 54: 51: 47: 43: 38: 35: 30: 19: 863: 847: 841: 824: 819: 798: 790: 770: 765: 755: 747: 737: 732: 722: 714: 704: 701:Bixler, J.S. 696: 686: 683:Bixler, J.S. 678: 668: 660: 651: 642: 633: 624: 615: 606: 597: 588: 579: 570: 561: 552: 540: 535: 521: 514: 510: 504: 491: 485: 474: 470:Wittgenstein 466: 452: 450: 445: 441: 435: 425: 421: 416: 376: 352: 335: 323: 311: 296: 289: 265: 256: 247: 235: 233: 231:philosophy. 216: 188: 187: 186: 179: 169: 33: 29: 244:Rudolf Otto 161:BL51 .S6257 879:Categories 805:SUNY Press 797:. (1993). 776:SUNY Press 757:Philosophy 528:References 444:alongside 240:naturalism 197:New Jersey 192:(1st imp. 122:0837118670 75:Philosophy 515:Thought: 475:Tractatus 315:phenomena 292:ineffable 268:intuition 225:mysticism 194:Princeton 89:Published 83:Mysticism 547:. P. 22. 359:acosmism 319:noumenon 317:and the 262:Synopsis 92:1952 by 71:Religion 59:Language 509:called 391:Bradley 383:Spinoza 379:Vedanta 136:1142510 67:Subject 62:English 833:  811:  782:  389:, and 250:, and 199:1952, 49:Author 387:Hegel 331:numen 108:Pages 831:ISBN 809:ISBN 780:ISBN 430:Hume 424:and 357:and 223:and 130:OCLC 117:ISBN 868:at 498:or 472:'s 455:by 149:201 111:169 881:: 803:, 543:. 385:, 381:, 215:. 81:, 77:, 73:, 400:“ 20:)

Index

Time and Eternity: an Essay in the Philosophy of Religion
Cover
Walter Terence Stace
Religion
Philosophy
Philosophy of Religion
Mysticism
Princeton University Press
ISBN
0837118670
OCLC
1142510
Dewey Decimal
LC Class
Princeton
New Jersey
Princeton University Press
Walter Terence Stace
Princeton University
Ceylon Civil Service
philosophy of religion
mysticism
phenomenalist
naturalism
Rudolf Otto
Immanuel Kant
intuition
negative divine
ineffable
positive divine

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑