Knowledge (XXG)

Median voting rule

Source đź“ť

86:: ask each member what is his peak, and take the average of all peaks. But this rule easily manipulable. For example, suppose Alice's peak is 30, George's peak is 40, and Chana's peak is 50. If all voters report their true peaks, the actual amount will be 40. But Alice may manipulate and say that her peak is actually 0; then the average will be 30, which is Alice's actual peak. Thus, Alice has gained from the manipulation. Similarly, any agent whose peak is different than the outcome has an incentive to manipulate and report a false peak. 968:. The median rule apparently contradicts this theorem, because it is strategyproof and it is not a dictatorship. In fact there is no contradiction: the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem applies only to rules that operate on the entire preference domain (that is, only to voting rules that can handle any set of preference rankings). In contrast, the median rule applies only to a restricted preference domain—the domain of single-peaked preferences. 103:: no voter can gain by reporting a false peak. In the above example, the median is 40, and it remains 40 even if Alice reports 0. In fact, as Alice's true peak is below the median, no false report by Alice can potentially decrease the median; Alice can only increase the median, but this will make her worse-off. 426:
single-peaked preferences (symmetry means that an outcome farther away from the peak should be less preferred than an outcome nearer to the peak, even if the outcomes are on different sides of the peak). The class of strategyproof mechanisms in this smaller domain is strictly larger than the class of
911:
In 1954, the Iranian Oil Consortium has adopted a median-like rule to determine Iran's total annual oil output. Annually, each member company's role was weighted by its fixed share of the total output. The chosen output, x, was the highest level such that the sum of the shares of members voting for
530:
Berga and Serizawa seek rules that are both strategyproof and satisfy a condition they call "no vetoer": no individual should be able to avoid any alternative to be the outcome by declaring some preference. They characterize generalized median rules as the only strategyproof rules on "minimally-rich
944:
are an attempt at applying the same voting rule to elections by asking voters to submit judgments (scores) for each candidate. However, the strategyproof nature of the median voting rule does not extend to choosing candidates unless the voters have single-peaked preferences over each candidate's
286:
The median rule is not the only strategyproof rule. One can construct alternative rules by adding fixed votes, that do not depend on the citizen votes. These fixed votes are called "phantoms". For every set of phantoms, the rule that chooses the median of the set of real votes + phantoms is
510:, that is: if the agent's peak is to the right of the outcome, and he moves his peak further to the right, then the outcome does not change; and similarly to the left. Conversely, every uncompromising rule is strategyproof. They prove that a rule is uncompromising if it has at most 2 290:
For example, suppose the votes are 30, 40, and 50. Without phantoms, the median rule selects 40. If we add two phantoms at 0, then the median rule selects 30; if we add two phantoms at 100, the median rule selects 50; if we add medians at 20 and 35, the median rule selects 35.
902:
In quadratic non-separable domains, the only strategyproof mecanisms are dictatorial. But in separable domains, there are multidimensional strategyproof mechanisms that are composed of one-dimensional strategyproof mechanisms, one for each coordinate.
264:
Similarly, consider a voter whose peak is above the median. Reporting a higher peak will not change the median; reporting a lower peak will either keep the median unchanged or decrease the median. In all cases, the voter does not
260:
Consider first a voter whose peak is below the median. Reporting a lower peak will not change the median; reporting a higher peak will either keep the median unchanged or increase the median. In all cases, the voter does not
889: 162:
Note that single-peakedness does not imply any particular distance-measure between the alternatives, and does not imply anything on alternatives at different sides of the peak. In particular, if a >
531:
domains". They proved that the unique maximal domain that includes a minimally-rich domain, which allows for the existence of strategyproof rules satisfying the "no vetoer" condition, is the domain of
665: 760: 500: 427:
generalized median rules. In particular, rules can be disturbed by discontinuity points. Their result allows to design rules that deal with feasibility constraints.
42:
along a one-dimensional domain. Each person votes by writing down his/her ideal value, and the rule selects a single value which is (in the basic mechanism) the
324:-1 phantoms at 50, then the median rule returns 50 if some ideal points are above and some are below 50; otherwise, it returns the vote closest to 50. 404:, even if they are not "peak only", are augmented median rules, that is, can be described by a variant of the median rule with some 2 parameters. 1282: 776: 77:
Each member has in mind an ideal decision, called his "peak". Each agent prefers the actual amount to be as close as possible to his peak.
538:
Barbera, Gul and Stacchetti also generalize the notions of single-peaked preferences and median voting rules to multidimensional settings.
938:
always selects the candidate preferred by the median voter (the candidate closest to the voter whose peak is the median of all peaks).
928:
mechanisms, in which each agent reports his/her full ranking over alternatives. The theorem says that, if the agents' preferences are
961: 1344: 564:
Border and Jordan generalize the notions of single-peaked preferences and median voting rules to multidimensional settings (see
159:
Once such a linear order exists, the median of any set of peaks can be computed by ordering the peaks along this linear order.
578: 419:
preferences. They prove that, even in this smaller domain, the strategyproof rules are exactly the generalized median rules.
273:, that is: no coalition has a coordinated manipulation that improves the utility of one of them without harming the others. 1349: 339:, strategyproof and Pareto-efficient for all single-peaked preferences if it is equivalent to a median rule with at most 941: 24: 1177:
BarberĂ , Salvador; Gul, Faruk; Stacchetti, Ennio (December 1993). "Generalized Median Voter Schemes and Committees".
1339: 1071:
Berga, Dolors; Serizawa, Shigehiro (January 2000). "Maximal Domain for Strategy-Proof Rules with One Public Good".
411:
single-peaked preferences. Several other works allow rules that handle only a subset of single-peaked preferences:
929: 347: 336: 112: 70: 763: 683: 556:- a generalization of single-peaked in which each agent is allowed to have an entire interval of ideal points. 1238:
Moulin, H. (August 1984). "Generalized condorcet-winners for single peaked and single-plateau preferences".
1098:
Massó, Jordi; Moreno de Barreda, Inés (June 2011). "On strategy-proofness and symmetric single-peakedness".
953:, but the rule will not be strategyproof in situations where voters have single-peaked preferences over the 565: 523: 396:
Moulin's characterizations consider only rules that are "peak only", that is, the rule depends only on the
965: 437: 522:. As a corollary, every uncompromising rule is continuous. However, an uncompromising rule that is also 519: 39: 115:. This means that there exists some linear ordering > of the alternatives, such that for each agent 350:
and strategyproof for all single-peaked preferences if it is equivalent to a median rule with at most
921: 20: 514:(that is, at most 2 points that may be elected even if they are not the peak of any voter), and its 1206:"A characterization of strategy-proof social choice functions for economies with pure public goods" 1205: 503: 294:
Here are some special cases of phantom-median rules, assuming all the votes are between 0 and 100:
270: 82: 1315: 1159: 1139: 1050: 1005: 532: 434:
preferences. In the one-dimensional setting, this is equivalent to utility functions of the form
518:(mapping each profile to the set of indices of real+phantom voters whose peak is elected) has a 1278: 950: 100: 56:
Many scenarions of group decision making involve a one-dimensional domain. Some examples are:
63:
Several people working in the same office have to decide on the air-conditioning temperature.
1307: 1270: 1247: 1220: 1186: 1151: 1115: 1107: 1080: 1040: 1032: 997: 935: 328: 66:
Parents of schoolchildren should decide how long the annual school vacation should be.
1333: 1009: 971:
Dummet and Farquharson present a sufficient condition for stability in voting games.
925: 1054: 357:
A rule is strategyproof for all single-peaked preferences iff it is equivalent to a
60:
Members of a city-council have to decide on the total amount of annual city budget.
1274: 1111: 1190: 1084: 964:
says that every strategyproof rule on three or more alternatives must be a
502:. In this domain, they prove that any strategyproof rule that respects the 1023:
Ching, Stephen (December 1997). "Strategy-proofness and 'median voters'".
1045: 1319: 1251: 1224: 1163: 1036: 1001: 884:{\displaystyle u_{i}(x)=-\sum _{j=1}^{m}a_{i,j}\cdot (x_{j}-p_{j})^{2}} 551: 1120: 111:
The median voting rule holds in any setting in which the agents have
95: 44: 1311: 1298:
Dummett, Michael; Farquharson, Robin (1961). "Stability in Voting".
1155: 545:
preferences, in which the maximal set may contain two alternatives.
269:
Using similar reasoning, one can prove that the median rule is also
988:
Moulin, H. (1980). "On strategy-proofness and single peakedness".
170:> b, then the agent may prefer either a to b or b to a. 541:
Barbera and Jackson characterized strategyproof rules for
400:
peaks. Ching proved that all rules that are strategyproof
1140:"Straightforward Elections, Unanimity and Phantom Voters" 372:
of voters. The rule returns the minimum over all subsets
256:
Here is a proof that the median rule is strategyproof:
407:
Moulin's characterizations require the rules to handle
660:{\displaystyle u_{i}(x)=\sum _{j=1}^{m}u_{i,j}(x_{j})} 779: 686: 581: 440: 313:-1 phantoms at 100, then the median rule returns the 302:-1 phantoms at 0, then the median rule returns the 883: 754: 659: 494: 1204:BarberĂ , Salvador; Jackson, Matthew (July 1994). 207:. In the basic mechanism, the chosen value when 99:of all votes. This simple change makes the rule 568:). They consider three classes of preferences: 430:Border and Jordan allow rules that handle only 361:of the following form. There are 2 parameters, 1138:Border, Kim C.; Jordan, J. S. (January 1983). 422:Masso and Moreno allow rules that handle only 415:Berga and Serizawa allow rules to handle only 8: 548:Moulin characterized strategyproof rules on 376:, of the maximum of (all peaks of voters in 193:. The values are sorted in ascending order 218:, which equals the median of values (when 1119: 1044: 875: 865: 852: 830: 820: 809: 784: 778: 755:{\displaystyle u_{i}(x)=-(x-p)^{T}A(x-p)} 728: 691: 685: 648: 629: 619: 608: 586: 580: 487: 481: 466: 445: 439: 331:proved the following characterizations: 980: 912:levels as high as x was at least 70%. 674:is a single-peaked utility function); 7: 1133: 1131: 1066: 1064: 1025:International Journal of Game Theory 93:determines the actual budget at the 495:{\displaystyle u_{i}(x)=-|x-p_{i}|} 949:This may be a reasonable model of 69:The public has to decide where to 14: 186:is asked to report the value of 16:Method for group decision-making 907:Application in the oil industry 73:along a one-dimensional street. 1144:The Review of Economic Studies 872: 845: 796: 790: 749: 737: 725: 712: 703: 697: 654: 641: 598: 592: 488: 467: 457: 451: 155:, then agent i prefers a to b. 145:, then agent i prefers a to b; 80:A simple way to decide is the 1: 962:Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem 222:is even, the chosen value is 392:Additional characterizations 19:Not to be confused with the 1100:Games and Economic Behavior 942:Highest median voting rules 560:Multidimensional extensions 25:highest median voting rules 1366: 1179:Journal of Economic Theory 1073:Journal of Economic Theory 957:(winner) of the election. 252:Proof of strategyproofness 18: 1275:10.1007/978-1-349-81487-9 1240:Social Choice and Welfare 1213:Social Choice and Welfare 1112:10.1016/j.geb.2010.12.001 113:single peaked preferences 898:are positive constants). 764:positive definite matrix 277:Generalized median rules 1345:Participatory budgeting 1265:Blair, John M. (1976). 762:where A is a symmetric 566:star-shaped preferences 1191:10.1006/jeth.1993.1069 1085:10.1006/jeth.1999.2579 885: 825: 756: 661: 624: 496: 249: 886: 805: 757: 662: 604: 497: 287:group-strategyproof. 231: 40:group decision-making 1350:Social choice theory 922:median voter theorem 777: 684: 579: 543:weakly-single-peaked 526:must be dictatorial. 516:elect correspondence 438: 282:Median with phantoms 21:median voter theorem 771:separable quadratic 769:Their intersection 504:unanimity criterion 271:group-strategyproof 83:average voting rule 1267:The Control of Oil 1252:10.1007/BF00452885 1225:10.1007/BF00193809 1037:10.1007/BF01813886 1002:10.1007/BF00128122 881: 752: 657: 533:convex preferences 492: 317:of all real votes. 306:of all real votes. 32:median voting rule 1340:Electoral systems 1284:978-1-349-81489-3 951:expressive voting 148:If b > a > 89:In contrast, the 71:locate a facility 1357: 1324: 1323: 1295: 1289: 1288: 1262: 1256: 1255: 1235: 1229: 1228: 1210: 1201: 1195: 1194: 1174: 1168: 1167: 1135: 1126: 1125: 1123: 1095: 1089: 1088: 1068: 1059: 1058: 1048: 1020: 1014: 1013: 985: 936:Condorcet method 916:Related concepts 890: 888: 887: 882: 880: 879: 870: 869: 857: 856: 841: 840: 824: 819: 789: 788: 761: 759: 758: 753: 733: 732: 696: 695: 666: 664: 663: 658: 653: 652: 640: 639: 623: 618: 591: 590: 501: 499: 498: 493: 491: 486: 485: 470: 450: 449: 233:choice = median( 36:median mechanism 1365: 1364: 1360: 1359: 1358: 1356: 1355: 1354: 1330: 1329: 1328: 1327: 1312:10.2307/1907685 1297: 1296: 1292: 1285: 1264: 1263: 1259: 1237: 1236: 1232: 1208: 1203: 1202: 1198: 1176: 1175: 1171: 1156:10.2307/2296962 1137: 1136: 1129: 1097: 1096: 1092: 1070: 1069: 1062: 1022: 1021: 1017: 987: 986: 982: 977: 918: 909: 896: 871: 861: 848: 826: 780: 775: 774: 724: 687: 682: 681: 672: 644: 625: 582: 577: 576: 562: 477: 441: 436: 435: 394: 385: 368:for any subset 366: 284: 279: 254: 245: 239: 228: 217: 205: 199: 191: 176: 168: 153: 135: 124: 109: 54: 48:of all votes. 28: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1363: 1361: 1353: 1352: 1347: 1342: 1332: 1331: 1326: 1325: 1290: 1283: 1257: 1246:(2): 127–147. 1230: 1196: 1185:(2): 262–289. 1169: 1127: 1106:(2): 467–484. 1090: 1060: 1031:(4): 473–490. 1015: 996:(4): 437–455. 979: 978: 976: 973: 917: 914: 908: 905: 900: 899: 894: 878: 874: 868: 864: 860: 855: 851: 847: 844: 839: 836: 833: 829: 823: 818: 815: 812: 808: 804: 801: 798: 795: 792: 787: 783: 767: 751: 748: 745: 742: 739: 736: 731: 727: 723: 720: 717: 714: 711: 708: 705: 702: 699: 694: 690: 675: 670: 656: 651: 647: 643: 638: 635: 632: 628: 622: 617: 614: 611: 607: 603: 600: 597: 594: 589: 585: 561: 558: 528: 527: 524:differentiable 512:phantom voters 508:uncompromising 490: 484: 480: 476: 473: 469: 465: 462: 459: 456: 453: 448: 444: 428: 420: 417:minimally-rich 402:and continuous 393: 390: 389: 388: 383: 364: 355: 344: 326: 325: 318: 307: 283: 280: 278: 275: 267: 266: 262: 253: 250: 243: 237: 226: 215: 203: 197: 189: 175: 172: 166: 157: 156: 151: 146: 133: 122: 108: 105: 75: 74: 67: 64: 61: 53: 50: 38:is a rule for 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1362: 1351: 1348: 1346: 1343: 1341: 1338: 1337: 1335: 1321: 1317: 1313: 1309: 1305: 1301: 1294: 1291: 1286: 1280: 1276: 1272: 1268: 1261: 1258: 1253: 1249: 1245: 1241: 1234: 1231: 1226: 1222: 1218: 1214: 1207: 1200: 1197: 1192: 1188: 1184: 1180: 1173: 1170: 1165: 1161: 1157: 1153: 1149: 1145: 1141: 1134: 1132: 1128: 1122: 1117: 1113: 1109: 1105: 1101: 1094: 1091: 1086: 1082: 1078: 1074: 1067: 1065: 1061: 1056: 1052: 1047: 1042: 1038: 1034: 1030: 1026: 1019: 1016: 1011: 1007: 1003: 999: 995: 991: 990:Public Choice 984: 981: 974: 972: 969: 967: 963: 958: 956: 952: 948: 943: 939: 937: 934:, then every 933: 932: 931:single-peaked 927: 926:ranked voting 923: 915: 913: 906: 904: 897: 876: 866: 862: 858: 853: 849: 842: 837: 834: 831: 827: 821: 816: 813: 810: 806: 802: 799: 793: 785: 781: 772: 768: 765: 746: 743: 740: 734: 729: 721: 718: 715: 709: 706: 700: 692: 688: 679: 676: 673: 667:, where each 649: 645: 636: 633: 630: 626: 620: 615: 612: 609: 605: 601: 595: 587: 583: 574: 571: 570: 569: 567: 559: 557: 555: 553: 546: 544: 539: 536: 534: 525: 521: 517: 513: 509: 505: 482: 478: 474: 471: 463: 460: 454: 446: 442: 433: 429: 425: 421: 418: 414: 413: 412: 410: 405: 403: 399: 391: 386: 379: 375: 371: 367: 360: 356: 353: 349: 345: 342: 338: 334: 333: 332: 330: 323: 320:If there are 319: 316: 312: 309:If there are 308: 305: 301: 298:If there are 297: 296: 295: 292: 288: 281: 276: 274: 272: 263: 259: 258: 257: 251: 248: 246: 236: 230: 225: 221: 214: 210: 206: 196: 192: 185: 181: 173: 171: 169: 160: 154: 147: 144: 140: 136: 129: 128: 127: 125: 118: 114: 107:Preconditions 106: 104: 102: 101:strategyproof 98: 97: 92: 87: 85: 84: 78: 72: 68: 65: 62: 59: 58: 57: 51: 49: 47: 46: 41: 37: 33: 26: 22: 1306:(1): 33–43. 1303: 1300:Econometrica 1299: 1293: 1266: 1260: 1243: 1239: 1233: 1216: 1212: 1199: 1182: 1178: 1172: 1147: 1143: 1103: 1099: 1093: 1079:(1): 39–61. 1076: 1072: 1046:10722/177668 1028: 1024: 1018: 993: 989: 983: 970: 966:dictatorship 959: 954: 946: 940: 930: 919: 910: 901: 892: 770: 677: 668: 572: 563: 549: 547: 542: 540: 537: 529: 520:closed graph 515: 511: 507: 431: 423: 416: 408: 406: 401: 397: 395: 381: 377: 373: 369: 362: 358: 354:+1 phantoms. 351: 343:-1 phantoms. 340: 327: 321: 314: 310: 303: 299: 293: 289: 285: 268: 255: 241: 234: 232: 223: 219: 212: 208: 201: 194: 187: 183: 179: 177: 164: 161: 158: 149: 142: 138: 131: 120: 116: 110: 94: 90: 88: 81: 79: 76: 55: 43: 35: 31: 29: 924:relates to 554:preferences 359:minmax rule 178:Each agent 91:median rule 1334:Categories 1150:(1): 153. 1121:2072/53376 975:References 346:A rule is 335:A rule is 211:is odd is 119:with peak 52:Motivation 1010:154508892 859:− 843:⋅ 807:∑ 803:− 744:− 719:− 710:− 678:Quadratic 606:∑ 573:Separable 475:− 464:− 432:quadratic 424:symmetric 348:anonymous 337:anonymous 182:in 1,..., 174:Procedure 1055:42830689 891:, where 200:≤ ... ≤ 1320:1907685 1164:2296962 955:outcome 552:plateau 550:single- 315:maximum 304:minimum 240:, ..., 216:(n+1)/2 1318:  1281:  1162:  1053:  1008:  947:score. 945:final 380:, and 329:Moulin 96:median 45:median 1316:JSTOR 1219:(3). 1209:(PDF) 1160:JSTOR 1051:S2CID 1006:S2CID 265:gain. 261:gain. 141:> 137:> 1279:ISBN 960:The 920:The 30:The 1308:doi 1271:doi 1248:doi 1221:doi 1187:doi 1152:doi 1116:hdl 1108:doi 1081:doi 1041:hdl 1033:doi 998:doi 895:i,j 671:i,j 506:is 409:all 227:n/2 130:If 34:or 23:or 1336:: 1314:. 1304:29 1302:. 1277:. 1269:. 1242:. 1217:11 1215:. 1211:. 1183:61 1181:. 1158:. 1148:50 1146:. 1142:. 1130:^ 1114:. 1104:72 1102:. 1077:90 1075:. 1063:^ 1049:. 1039:. 1029:26 1027:. 1004:. 994:35 992:. 766:); 535:. 387:). 247:). 229:): 126:: 1322:. 1310:: 1287:. 1273:: 1254:. 1250:: 1244:1 1227:. 1223:: 1193:. 1189:: 1166:. 1154:: 1124:. 1118:: 1110:: 1087:. 1083:: 1057:. 1043:: 1035:: 1012:. 1000:: 893:a 877:2 873:) 867:j 863:p 854:j 850:x 846:( 838:j 835:, 832:i 828:a 822:m 817:1 814:= 811:j 800:= 797:) 794:x 791:( 786:i 782:u 773:( 750:) 747:p 741:x 738:( 735:A 730:T 726:) 722:p 716:x 713:( 707:= 704:) 701:x 698:( 693:i 689:u 680:( 669:v 655:) 650:j 646:x 642:( 637:j 634:, 631:i 627:u 621:m 616:1 613:= 610:j 602:= 599:) 596:x 593:( 588:i 584:u 575:( 489:| 483:i 479:p 472:x 468:| 461:= 458:) 455:x 452:( 447:i 443:u 398:n 384:S 382:b 378:S 374:S 370:S 365:S 363:b 352:n 341:n 322:n 311:n 300:n 244:n 242:p 238:1 235:p 224:p 220:n 213:p 209:n 204:n 202:p 198:1 195:p 190:i 188:p 184:n 180:i 167:i 165:p 152:i 150:p 143:b 139:a 134:i 132:p 123:i 121:p 117:i 27:.

Index

median voter theorem
highest median voting rules
group decision-making
median
locate a facility
average voting rule
median
strategyproof
single peaked preferences
group-strategyproof
Moulin
anonymous
anonymous
unanimity criterion
closed graph
differentiable
convex preferences
plateau
star-shaped preferences
positive definite matrix
median voter theorem
ranked voting
single-peaked
Condorcet method
Highest median voting rules
expressive voting
Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem
dictatorship
doi
10.1007/BF00128122

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑