Knowledge (XXG)

Monadology

Source 📝

212:(§18), Leibniz posits quantitative differences in perfection between monads which leads to a hierarchical ordering. The basic order is three-tiered: (1) entelechies or created monads (§48), (2) souls or entelechies with perception and memory (§19), and (3) spirits or rational souls (§82). Whatever is said about the lower ones (entelechies) is valid for the higher (souls and spirits) but not vice versa. As none of them is without a body (§72), there is a corresponding hierarchy of (1) living beings and animals (2), the latter being either (2) non-reasonable or (3) reasonable. The degree of perfection in each case corresponds to cognitive abilities and only spirits or reasonable animals are able to grasp the ideas of both the world and its creator. Some monads have power over others because they can perceive with greater clarity, but primarily, one monad is said to dominate another if it contains the reasons for the actions of other(s). Leibniz believed that any body, such as the body of an animal or man, has one dominant monad which controls the others within it. This dominant monad is often referred to as the soul. 235:
each organ of an animal, each drop of its bodily fluids is also a similar garden or a similar pond". There are no interactions between different monads nor between entelechies and their bodies but everything is regulated by the pre-established harmony (§§78–9). Much like how one clock may be in synchronicity with another, but the first clock is not caused by the second (or vice versa), rather they are only keeping the same time because the last person to wind them set them to the same time. So it is with monads; they may seem to cause each other, but rather they are, in a sense, "wound" by God's pre-established harmony, and thus appear to be in synchronicity. Leibniz concludes that "if we could understand the order of the universe well enough, we would find that it surpasses all the wishes of the wisest people, and that it is impossible to make it better than it is—not merely in respect of the whole in general, but also in respect of ourselves in particular" (§90).
251:
because a monad is a “simple substance” and God is simplest of all substances, He cannot be broken down any further. This means that all monads perceive “with varying degrees of perception, except for God, who perceives all monads with utter clarity”. This superior perception of God then would apply in much the same way that he says a dominant monad controls our soul, all other monads associated with it would, essentially, shade themselves towards Him. With all monads being created by the ultimate monad and shading themselves in the image of this ultimate monad, Leibniz argues that it would be impossible to conceive of a more perfect world because all things in the world are created by and imitating the best possible monad.
239:
likewise substance itself. The only things that could be called real were utterly simple beings of psychic activity "endowed with perception and appetite." The other objects, which we call matter, are merely phenomena of these simple perceivers. "Leibniz says, 'I don't really eliminate body, but reduce it to what it is. For I show that corporeal mass , which is thought to have something over and above simple substances, is not a substance, but a phenomenon resulting from simple substances, which alone have unity and absolute reality.' (G II 275/AG 181)" Leibniz's philosophy is sometimes called "'
945: 625: 74: 22: 234:
Composite substances or matter are "actually sub-divided without end" and have the properties of their infinitesimal parts (§65). A notorious passage (§67) explains that "each portion of matter can be conceived as like a garden full of plants, or like a pond full of fish. But each branch of a plant,
250:
Leibniz uses his theory of Monads to support his argument that we live in the best of all possible worlds. He uses his basis of perception but not interaction among monads to explain that all monads must draw their essence from one ultimate monad. He then claims that this ultimate monad would be God
218:
God is also said to be a simple substance (§47) but it is the only one necessary (§§38–9) and without a body attached (§72). Monads perceive others "with varying degrees of clarity, except for God, who perceives all monads with utter clarity". God could take any and all perspectives, knowing of both
238:
In his day, atoms were proposed to be the smallest division of matter. Within Leibniz's theory, however, substances are not technically real, so monads are not the smallest part of matter, rather they are the only things which are, in fact, real. To Leibniz, space and time were an illusion, and
243:
idealism' because these substances are psychic rather than material". That is to say, they are mind-like substances, not possessing spatial reality. "In other words, in the Leibnizian monadology, simple substances are mind-like entities that do not, strictly speaking, exist in space but that
628: 392:
Translated by Frederic Henry Hedge. "Leibniz's vestige view of God's creative act is employed to support his view of substance as an inherently active being possessed of its own dynamic force" in David Scott, "Leibniz model of creation and his doctrine of substance",
227:
of the Divinity" (§47). Any perfection comes from being created while imperfection is a limitation of nature (§42). The monads are unaffected by each other, but each have a unique way of expressing themselves in the universe, in accordance with God's infinite will.
151:, the word and the idea, belongs to the Western philosophical tradition and has been used by various authors. Leibniz, who was exceptionally well-read, could not have ignored this, but he did not use it himself until mid-1696 when he was sending for print his 126:. There are three original manuscripts of the text: the first written by Leibniz and glossed with corrections and two further emended copies with some corrections appearing in one but not the other. Leibniz himself inserted references to the paragraphs of his 223:. As well as that God in all his power would know the universe from each of the infinite perspectives at the same time, and so his perspectives—his thoughts—"simply are monads". Creation is a permanent state, thus " are generated, so to speak, by continual 244:
represent the universe from a unique perspective." It is the harmony between the perceptions of the monads which creates what we call substances, but that does not mean the substances are real in and of themselves.
208:' and described as 'a simple substance' (§§1, 19). When Leibniz says that monads are 'simple,' he means that "which is one, has no parts and is therefore indivisible". Relying on the Greek etymology of the word 163:. Leibniz surmised that there are indefinitely many substances individually 'programmed' to act in a predetermined way, each substance being coordinated with all the others. This is the 699: 639: 643: 155:. Apparently he found with it a convenient way to expound his own philosophy as it was elaborated in this period. What he proposed can be seen as a modification of 972: 736: 692: 85:
from 1712 to September 1714, Leibniz wrote two short texts in French which were meant as concise expositions of his philosophy. After his death,
617: 599: 577: 370:
Audi Robert, ed. "Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm." The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge; Cambridge University Press (1999): 193.
359:
On pourrait donner le nom d'entéléchies à toutes les substances simples ou Monades créées, car elles ont en elles une certaine perfection
948: 685: 929: 900: 841: 591: 569: 967: 824: 94: 749: 731: 977: 770: 220: 708: 260: 890: 863: 814: 760: 726: 164: 819: 765: 614:, English translation, links, scalable text and printable version. Downloadable as pdf, doc or djvu files. 97:
and collaborators published translations in German and Latin of the second text which came to be known as
742: 669: 795: 880: 808: 168: 132:("Theodicy", i.e. a justification of God), sending the interested reader there for more details. 61: 398: 200:
As far as Leibniz allows just one type of element in the building of the universe his system is
851: 780: 595: 587: 573: 565: 44: 447:
Pestana, Mark. "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz." World Philosophers & Their Works (2000): 1–4.
435: 422: 380: 801: 790: 557: 56: 118: 90: 36: 910: 469:
Burnham, Douglas. "Gottfried Leibniz: Metaphysics." Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
456:
Burnham, Douglas. "Gottfried Leibniz: Metaphysics." Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
408:
Burnham, Douglas. "Gottfried Leibniz: Metaphysics." Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
345:
Burnham, Douglas. "Gottfried Leibniz: Metaphysics." Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
128: 830: 755: 484: 316: 187:
begins with a description of monads (proceeding from simple to complicated instances),
961: 785: 775: 523: 504: 315:
There is no indication that Leibniz has 'borrowed' it from a particular author, e.g.
271: 171:, but at the cost of declaring any interaction between substances a mere appearance. 156: 73: 21: 224: 657:(1981), with facsimile of Leibniz's manuscript, and introduction by Gustavo Bueno 846: 663: 611: 240: 52: 160: 48: 677: 205: 857: 836: 634: 320: 654: 289:
Lamarra A., Contexte Génétique et PremiÚre Réception de la Monadologie,
470: 457: 409: 346: 147: 201: 82: 434:
Look, Brandon C. "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz." Stanford University,
421:
Look, Brandon C. "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz." Stanford University,
379:
Look, Brandon C. "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz." Stanford University,
649: 72: 20: 681: 204:. The unique element has been 'given the general name monad or 51:. It is a short text which presents, in some 90 paragraphs, a 662: 584:
Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Leibniz and the Monadology
436:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/leibniz
423:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/leibniz
381:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/leibniz
650:
A version of this work, lightly edited for easier reading
334:
Leibniz's "New System" and associated contemporary texts
105:
they had assumed that it was the French original of the
87:
Principes de la nature et de la grùce fondés en raison
872: 715: 101:. Without having seen the Dutch publication of the 522: 503: 306:, edition Ă©tablie par E. Boutroux, Paris LGF 1991 190:then it turns to their principle or creator and 109:which in fact remained unpublished until 1840. 179:The rhetorical strategy adopted by Leibniz in 693: 8: 193:finishes by using both to explain the world. 112:The German translation appeared in 1720 as 77:The first manuscript page of the Monadology 700: 686: 678: 93:, appeared in French in the Netherlands. 564:, University of Pittsburgh Press, 1991, 282: 323:, to mention just two popular sources 7: 673:. New York: Robert Appleton Company. 489:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 471:http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H8 458:http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H8 410:http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H8 347:http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H8 973:Works by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 47:'s best known works of his later 14: 901:New Essays on Human Understanding 842:Transcendental law of homogeneity 661:Herbermann, Charles, ed. (1913). 655:French, Latin and Spanish edition 944: 943: 646:(1999), by George MacDonald Ross 623: 89:, which was intended for prince 540:Antognazza, Maria Rosa (2016). 183:is fairly obvious as the text 114:LehrsĂ€tze ĂŒber die Monadologie 1: 930:Leibniz–Clarke correspondence 332:Woolhouse R. and Francks R., 122:printed the Latin version as 16:Philosophical work by Leibniz 521:Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 502:Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 336:, Cambridge Univ. Press 1997 750:Characteristica universalis 732:Best of all possible worlds 633:public domain audiobook at 485:"Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz" 116:and the following year the 994: 771:Identity of indiscernibles 562:G. W. Leibniz's Monadology 544:. Oxford University Press. 221:potentiality and actuality 941: 709:Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 891:Discourse on Metaphysics 159:developed by latter-day 81:During his last stay in 864:Well-founded phenomenon 815:Pre-established harmony 727:Alternating series test 165:pre-established harmony 968:1714 non-fiction books 620:(1898) by Robert Latta 491:. Stanford University. 124:Principia philosophiae 78: 40: 26: 743:Calculus ratiocinator 670:Catholic Encyclopedia 76: 24: 881:De Arte Combinatoria 809:Mathesis universalis 737:Calculus controversy 586:, Routledge (2000), 640:English translation 618:English translation 558:Nicholas Rescher N. 361:(áŒ”Ï‡ÎżÏ…ÏƒÎč τ᜞ ጐΜτΔλές) 796:Leibniz's notation 293:128 (2007) 311–323 79: 43:, 1714) is one of 27: 978:Metaphysics books 955: 954: 933:(1715–1716) 852:Universal science 825:Sufficient reason 781:Law of continuity 600:978-0-415-17113-7 578:978-0-8229-5449-1 483:Look, Brandon C. 291:Revue de Synthese 169:mind-body problem 167:which solved the 45:Gottfried Leibniz 985: 947: 946: 934: 926: 916: 906: 896: 886: 802:Lingua generalis 702: 695: 688: 679: 674: 666: 627: 626: 546: 545: 537: 531: 530: 528: 518: 512: 511: 509: 499: 493: 492: 480: 474: 467: 461: 454: 448: 445: 439: 432: 426: 419: 413: 406: 400: 390: 384: 377: 371: 368: 362: 356: 350: 343: 337: 330: 324: 313: 307: 300: 294: 287: 993: 992: 988: 987: 986: 984: 983: 982: 958: 957: 956: 951: 937: 932: 924: 914: 904: 894: 884: 868: 720: 718: 717:Mathematics and 711: 706: 660: 624: 608: 554: 549: 539: 538: 534: 520: 519: 515: 501: 500: 496: 482: 481: 477: 468: 464: 455: 451: 446: 442: 433: 429: 420: 416: 407: 403: 391: 387: 378: 374: 369: 365: 357: 353: 344: 340: 331: 327: 314: 310: 301: 297: 288: 284: 280: 257: 177: 143: 138: 119:Acta Eruditorum 95:Christian Wolff 91:Eugene of Savoy 71: 17: 12: 11: 5: 991: 989: 981: 980: 975: 970: 960: 959: 953: 952: 942: 939: 938: 936: 935: 927: 917: 907: 897: 887: 876: 874: 870: 869: 867: 866: 861: 854: 849: 844: 839: 834: 831:Salva veritate 827: 822: 817: 812: 805: 798: 793: 788: 783: 778: 773: 768: 763: 758: 756:Compossibility 753: 746: 739: 734: 729: 723: 721: 716: 713: 712: 707: 705: 704: 697: 690: 682: 676: 675: 658: 652: 647: 637: 621: 615: 612:The Monadology 607: 606:External links 604: 603: 602: 580: 553: 550: 548: 547: 532: 513: 494: 475: 462: 449: 440: 427: 414: 401: 385: 372: 363: 351: 338: 325: 317:Giordano Bruno 308: 304:La Monadologie 302:Leibniz G.W., 295: 281: 279: 276: 275: 274: 269: 256: 253: 195: 194: 191: 188: 181:The Monadology 176: 173: 142: 139: 137: 134: 99:The Monadology 70: 67: 41:La Monadologie 15: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 990: 979: 976: 974: 971: 969: 966: 965: 963: 950: 940: 931: 928: 923: 922: 918: 913: 912: 908: 903: 902: 898: 893: 892: 888: 883: 882: 878: 877: 875: 871: 865: 862: 860: 859: 855: 853: 850: 848: 845: 843: 840: 838: 835: 833: 832: 828: 826: 823: 821: 818: 816: 813: 811: 810: 806: 804: 803: 799: 797: 794: 792: 791:Leibniz's gap 789: 787: 786:Leibniz wheel 784: 782: 779: 777: 776:Individuation 774: 772: 769: 767: 764: 762: 759: 757: 754: 752: 751: 747: 745: 744: 740: 738: 735: 733: 730: 728: 725: 724: 722: 714: 710: 703: 698: 696: 691: 689: 684: 683: 680: 672: 671: 665: 664:"Monad"  659: 656: 653: 651: 648: 645: 641: 638: 636: 632: 631: 622: 619: 616: 613: 610: 609: 605: 601: 597: 593: 592:0-415-17113-X 589: 585: 581: 579: 575: 571: 570:0-8229-5449-4 567: 563: 559: 556: 555: 551: 543: 536: 533: 527: 526: 517: 514: 508: 507: 498: 495: 490: 486: 479: 476: 472: 466: 463: 459: 453: 450: 444: 441: 437: 431: 428: 424: 418: 415: 411: 405: 402: 399: 396: 389: 386: 382: 376: 373: 367: 364: 360: 355: 352: 348: 342: 339: 335: 329: 326: 322: 318: 312: 309: 305: 299: 296: 292: 286: 283: 277: 273: 272:Perspectivism 270: 268: 267: 263: 259: 258: 254: 252: 249: 245: 242: 236: 233: 229: 226: 222: 217: 213: 211: 207: 203: 199: 192: 189: 186: 185: 184: 182: 174: 172: 170: 166: 162: 158: 157:occasionalism 154: 150: 149: 140: 135: 133: 131: 130: 125: 121: 120: 115: 110: 108: 104: 100: 96: 92: 88: 84: 75: 68: 66: 64: 63: 58: 54: 50: 46: 42: 38: 34: 33: 23: 19: 920: 919: 909: 899: 889: 879: 856: 829: 807: 800: 748: 741: 668: 629: 583: 561: 541: 535: 524: 516: 505: 497: 488: 478: 465: 452: 443: 430: 417: 404: 394: 388: 375: 366: 358: 354: 341: 333: 328: 311: 303: 298: 290: 285: 266:a posteriori 265: 261: 247: 246: 237: 231: 230: 225:fulgurations 215: 214: 209: 197: 196: 180: 178: 152: 146: 144: 127: 123: 117: 113: 111: 106: 102: 98: 86: 80: 60: 31: 30: 28: 18: 847:Rationalism 582:Savile A., 136:Metaphysics 107:Monadology, 53:metaphysics 962:Categories 921:Monadology 761:Difference 719:philosophy 644:commentary 630:Monadology 552:References 525:Monadology 506:Monadology 241:panpsychic 210:entelechie 161:Cartesians 153:New System 57:substances 55:of simple 49:philosophy 32:Monadology 25:Monadology 911:ThĂ©odicĂ©e 820:Plenitude 397:3 (1998) 206:entelechy 129:ThĂ©odicĂ©e 103:Principes 949:Category 858:Vis viva 837:Theodicy 766:Dynamism 635:LibriVox 321:John Dee 262:A priori 255:See also 202:monistic 542:Leibniz 175:Summary 141:Context 925:(1714) 915:(1710) 905:(1704) 895:(1686) 885:(1666) 598:  590:  576:  568:  395:Animus 83:Vienna 62:monads 37:French 873:Works 278:Notes 232:(III) 148:monad 59:, or 642:and 596:ISBN 588:ISBN 574:ISBN 566:ISBN 264:and 248:(IV) 216:(II) 145:The 69:Text 29:The 594:, 319:or 198:(I) 964:: 667:. 572:, 560:, 487:. 65:. 39:: 701:e 694:t 687:v 529:. 510:. 473:. 460:. 438:. 425:. 412:. 383:. 349:. 35:(

Index


French
Gottfried Leibniz
philosophy
metaphysics
substances
monads

Vienna
Eugene of Savoy
Christian Wolff
Acta Eruditorum
Théodicée
monad
occasionalism
Cartesians
pre-established harmony
mind-body problem
monistic
entelechy
potentiality and actuality
fulgurations
panpsychic
A priori and a posteriori
Perspectivism
Giordano Bruno
John Dee
http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H8
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/leibniz

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑