Knowledge

Commensurability (ethics)

Source đź“ť

283:
example, if one is trying to decide on some nice afternoon whether they should stay in to do work or go for a walk, on this view of practical reason they will compare the merits of these two options. If going for a walk is the better or more reasonable course of action, they should put aside their books and go for a stroll. The topic of incommensurability—and the topic of incomparability in particular—is especially important to those who advocate this view of practical reason. For if one's options in certain circumstances are of incomparable value, he or she cannot settle the question of what to do by choosing the better option. When the competing options are incomparable, then by definition neither is better than the other.
198:. She does this by denying that the three trichotomous comparisons are the only ones on offer. She defends the existence of a fourth comparison, which she calls 'parity'. Luke Elson has criticised this argument, claiming that the apparent possibility of parity is really an artefact of the vagueness of the (trichotomous) comparisons involved. 133:
There are four main philosophical accounts of incommensurability or incomparability. Their task is to explain (or explain away) the phenomenon, and the small-improvement argument. Some philosophers are pluralists about the phenomenon: they think that (for example) genuine incomparability might be the
120:
Here is the crux of the small-improvement argument: if banking is exactly equally as good as professor, and banking+ is better than banking, then banking+ must be better than professor. But this seems very implausible: if banking and professor were so different that we could not say that professor is
282:
typically aims for a description of the principles relevant in answering the question, "What is to be done in this or that circumstance?" On one popular view, answers to this question can be found by comparing the relative strengths of the various values or norms in play in some given situation. For
241:
Incomparability has figured prominently in several philosophical debates concerning moral and rational action. In general, incomparability can add complications to any view according to which one ought to do the best thing that one can, or the better of two options. If the options are incomparable,
116:
Suppose also that in order to tempt you, the bankers offer you a tiny pay rise, perhaps 5 cents a year. This new banking job (often called 'banking+') is clearly better than banking, albeit only by a tiny amount. You could (under normal circumstances) never rationally choose banking over banking+:
102:
The purpose of such examples is to show that none of the trichotomous comparisons apply. Here is an example. Suppose that (for you, taking everything into account) a certain job as a professor and a certain job as a banker are such that neither seems better than the other. The professor job offers
124:
This seems to show that one of our assumptions was incorrect. Defenders of incomparability will say it is most plausible that it is the assumption that banking and philosophy are equally good that is incorrect. So they conclude that this assumption as false, and thus that none of the trichotomous
156:
According to this view, apparent incomparability is merely ignorance. An advantage of this account is that the various puzzles surrounding incomparability dissolve rather quickly. Choice between incomparable options is no more than choice between options when we do not know which is better.
222:
minimum number of grains of sand needed to count as a heap, or hairs required to count as non-bald? If there is no precise number, only a rough range, then these are instances of vagueness. On one set of theories of vagueness, it is
103:
more freedom and security, and the banking job offers more money and excitement. But we might say that though they are good in different ways, they are just too different to be compared with one of the trichotomous comparisons.
149:, and when it seems like none of the three trichotomous comparisons apply, in fact one of them does but we do not know which. This is where the small-improvement argument goes wrong: one of the trichotomous comparisons 217:
The argument for this position is complex, and how 'incomparability as vagueness' is to be understood depends on one's theory of vagueness. But the main idea behind the theory is fairly simple. What is the
230:
In the small-improvement argument, the incomparability as vagueness view might say that it is indeterminate whether banking is better or worse than philosophy, or precisely equally good.
109:
But what about the third? Might the jobs be exactly equally good? The small improvement argument is supposed to show that they could not. Suppose for the sake of argument that they
275:
has argued that incommensurability undermines the 'rationalistic' view of human action according to which distinctively rational action is doing what one has most reason to do.
233:
One taxonomic complication is distinguishing the view that incomparability is vagueness, combined with epistemicism about vagueness, from epistemicism about incomparability.
90:
are betterness, worseness, and equal goodness. For example, one artist, drawing, or cup of coffee might be better or worse than another, or precisely equally as good as it.
55:
when they cannot be 'traded off' against each other: for example, if there is no set amount of freedom that would compensate for a certain loss of security, or vice versa.
106:
Let's suppose that this means that the banking job is not better, and the professor job is not better. This seems to rule out two of the three trichotomous comparisons.
253:
think that the morally right thing to do is what promotes the most overall good. But if two actions produce incomparable outcomes, it may be that neither is better.
292: 40:(or incommensurate, or incomparable) when they do not share a common standard of measurement or cannot be compared to each other in a certain way. 121:
better, and we could not say that banking is better, then how could adding 5 cents a year to a huge salary make the difference?
93:
When two items are incomparable, none of the trichotomous comparisons holds between them (or at least it seems that way).
137:
One way to understand the difference between the theories is to see how they respond to the small-improvement argument.
493: 70:
if and only if: it is not true that one is better, that the other is better, or that they are exactly equally good.
207: 74:
This page is concerned almost entirely with the second phenomenon. For clarity, the term 'incomparable' is used.
164:. In particular, it is hard to see how we could be ignorant of the kinds of facts involved in incomparability. 43:
There is a cluster of related ideas, and many philosophers use the terms differently. On one common usage:
227:
how many heaps or hairs are required. Perhaps our language simply does not specify a sharp boundary.
160:
The main objection to this kind of view is that it seems very implausible, for similar reasons to
427: 380: 345: 182:
John Nolt provides a formal logical treatment of genuine incomparability and related topics in
419: 337: 25: 411: 372: 329: 279: 256:
The topic of incommensurability has also frequently arisen in discussions of the version of
250: 214:. This theory says that it is vague or indeterminate which trichotomous comparison applies. 29: 297: 242:
it may be that neither is better. (Depending on which view of incomparability is true.)
487: 431: 349: 33: 376: 161: 21: 261: 257: 452: 272: 83: 423: 341: 399: 211: 384: 194:
Ruth Chang has argued that (at least some of the time), options may be
17: 363:
Raz, Joseph (1985). "Value Incommensurability: Some Preliminaries".
415: 333: 96:
The clearest way of arguing that two options are incomparable is a
400:"Heaps and Chains: Is the Chaining Argument for Parity a Sorites?" 117:
they are the same in every way, except that the latter pays more.
471:
Incomparable Values: Analysis, Axiomatics, and Applications.
176:. Neither option is better, and they are not equally good. 457:
Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason.
196:
comparable even if they are not trichotomously comparable
172:
Joseph Raz has argued that in cases of incomparability,
78:
Trichotomous comparisons and small-improvement arguments
320:
Chang, Ruth (2002-07-01). "The Possibility of Parity".
179:
On this view, the small-improvement argument is sound.
134:
correct account in some cases, and parity in others.
145:
One possibility is that this is all a mistake: that
444:'Incommensurability and Agency' in the Chang book. 237:Philosophical implications of incomparability 8: 459:Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997. 293:Commensurability (philosophy of science) 51:(for example, freedom and security) are 365:Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 309: 206:Finally, a set of philosophers led by 153:apply between banking and philosophy. 473:New York and London: Routledge, 2022. 7: 315: 313: 210:has argued that incomparability is 147:there is no genuine incomparability 141:Epistemicism about incomparability 14: 464:Natural Law and Natural Rights. 278:Philosophical reflection about 480:Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986. 466:Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980. 129:Theories of incommensurability 1: 377:10.1093/aristotelian/86.1.117 202:Incomparability as vagueness 162:epistemicism about vagueness 98:small-improvement argument. 510: 398:Elson, Luke (2014-04-01). 478:The Morality of Freedom. 113:precisely equally good. 88:trichotomous comparisons 260:theory associated with 168:Genuine incomparability 82:In terminology due to 174:no comparison applies 184:Incomparable Values 125:comparisons apply. 494:Concepts in ethics 186:(see references). 60:options or choices 251:Consequentialists 501: 445: 442: 436: 435: 395: 389: 388: 360: 354: 353: 317: 280:practical reason 509: 508: 504: 503: 502: 500: 499: 498: 484: 483: 449: 448: 443: 439: 397: 396: 392: 362: 361: 357: 319: 318: 311: 306: 298:Value pluralism 289: 270: 268:Rational choice 248: 239: 204: 192: 170: 143: 131: 80: 53:incommensurable 38:incommensurable 12: 11: 5: 507: 505: 497: 496: 486: 485: 482: 481: 474: 467: 462:Finnis, John. 460: 447: 446: 437: 416:10.1086/674844 410:(3): 557–571. 390: 355: 334:10.1086/339673 328:(4): 659–688. 308: 307: 305: 302: 301: 300: 295: 288: 285: 269: 266: 247: 244: 238: 235: 203: 200: 191: 188: 169: 166: 142: 139: 130: 127: 79: 76: 72: 71: 64:incommensurate 56: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 506: 495: 492: 491: 489: 479: 476:Raz, Joseph. 475: 472: 468: 465: 461: 458: 454: 451: 450: 441: 438: 433: 429: 425: 421: 417: 413: 409: 405: 401: 394: 391: 386: 382: 378: 374: 370: 366: 359: 356: 351: 347: 343: 339: 335: 331: 327: 323: 316: 314: 310: 303: 299: 296: 294: 291: 290: 286: 284: 281: 276: 274: 267: 265: 263: 259: 254: 252: 245: 243: 236: 234: 231: 228: 226: 225:indeterminate 221: 215: 213: 209: 201: 199: 197: 189: 187: 185: 180: 177: 175: 167: 165: 163: 158: 154: 152: 148: 140: 138: 135: 128: 126: 122: 118: 114: 112: 107: 104: 100: 99: 94: 91: 89: 85: 77: 75: 69: 65: 61: 57: 54: 50: 46: 45: 44: 41: 39: 35: 31: 27: 23: 19: 477: 470: 463: 456: 440: 407: 403: 393: 368: 364: 358: 325: 321: 277: 271: 264:and others. 255: 249: 240: 232: 229: 224: 219: 216: 205: 195: 193: 183: 181: 178: 173: 171: 159: 155: 150: 146: 144: 136: 132: 123: 119: 115: 110: 108: 105: 101: 97: 95: 92: 87: 86:, the three 81: 73: 68:incomparable 67: 63: 59: 52: 48: 42: 37: 15: 469:Nolt, John 453:Chang, Ruth 371:: 117–134. 262:John Finnis 258:natural law 208:John Broome 455:(editor). 304:References 273:Joseph Raz 84:Ruth Chang 432:170448389 424:0014-1704 350:170753406 342:0014-1704 212:vagueness 488:Category 287:See also 246:Morality 385:4545040 220:precise 30:reasons 430:  422:  404:Ethics 383:  348:  340:  322:Ethics 190:Parity 49:values 36:) are 22:values 20:, two 18:ethics 428:S2CID 381:JSTOR 346:S2CID 34:goods 32:, or 26:norms 420:ISSN 338:ISSN 151:does 62:are 58:Two 47:Two 24:(or 412:doi 408:124 373:doi 330:doi 326:112 111:are 66:or 16:In 490:: 426:. 418:. 406:. 402:. 379:. 369:86 367:. 344:. 336:. 324:. 312:^ 28:, 434:. 414:: 387:. 375:: 352:. 332::

Index

ethics
values
norms
reasons
goods
Ruth Chang
epistemicism about vagueness
John Broome
vagueness
Consequentialists
natural law
John Finnis
Joseph Raz
practical reason
Commensurability (philosophy of science)
Value pluralism


doi
10.1086/339673
ISSN
0014-1704
S2CID
170753406
doi
10.1093/aristotelian/86.1.117
JSTOR
4545040
"Heaps and Chains: Is the Chaining Argument for Parity a Sorites?"
doi

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑