Knowledge (XXG)

Description-experience gap

Source 📝

209:
effects. Although doctors learn about the same probabilities and descriptions of the side effects, their perspective is also shaped by experience: doctors have the direct experience of vaccinating patients and they are more likely to recognize the unlikelihood of the side effects. Due to the different ways in which doctors and patients learn about the side effects, there is potential disagreement on the necessity and safety of vaccination.
147:, people are allowed to respond to a number of prospects. Presumably, they form their own estimations for the probabilities of the outcomes through sampling. However, some studies rely on people making decisions for a small sample of prospects. Due to the small samples, people may not even experience the low probability event, and this might influence peoples’ underweighting of the rare events. However, 163:. The recency effect shows that greater weight or value is assigned to more recent events. Given that rare events are uncommon, the more common events are more likely to take recency and therefore be weighted more than rare events. The recency effect, then, may be responsible for the underweighting of rare events in decisions made from experience. Given that 123:
outcomes were more unlikely than they really were. The effect has been observed in studies involving repeated and small samples of choices. However, people tended to choose the riskier choice when deciding from experience for tasks that are framed in terms of gains, and this, too, is in contrast with decisions made from description.
79:, the decision weight of described prospects are considered differently depending on whether the prospects have a high or low probability and the nature of the outcomes. Specifically, people's decisions differ depending on whether the described prospects are framed as gains or losses, and whether the outcomes are sure or probable. 175:
is a basic tendency to avoid delayed outcomes: alternatives with positive rare events are on average advantageous only in the long term; while alternatives with negative rare events are on average disadvantageous in the long term. Hence, focusing on short term outcomes produces underweighting of rare
90:
are those where the two possible choices both result in a reduction of a certain resource. An outcome is said to be sure when its probability is absolutely certain, or very close to 1. A probable outcome is one that is comparably more unlikely than the sure outcome. For described prospects, people
47:
In both described and experienced choice tasks, the experimental task usually involves selecting between one of two possible choices that lead to certain outcomes. The outcome could be a gain or a loss and the probabilities of these outcomes vary. Of the two choices, one is probabilistically safer
208:
has been illustrated: the difference in opinions on vaccination between doctors and patients. Patients who learn about vaccination are usually exposed to only information regarding the probabilities of the side effects of the vaccines so they are likely to overweight the likelihood of these side
139:
towards gains for participants in the experience task is virtually identical to the level of risk-taking towards losses for participants in the description task. The same effect is observed for gains versus losses in experience and description tasks. There are a few explanations and factors that
122:
Contrary to the results obtained by prospect theory, people tended to underweight the probabilities of rare outcomes when they made decisions from experience. That is, they in general tended to choose the more probable outcome much more often than the rare outcomes; they behaved as if the rare
184:
when learning the outcomes and their probabilities. Biases for more salient memories, then, may be the reason for greater risk seeking in gains choices in experience-based studies. The assumption here is that a more improbable but greater reward may produce a more salient memory.
126:
As demonstrated above, decisions appear to be made very differently depending on whether choices are made from experience or description; that is, a description-experience gap has been demonstrated in decision making studies. The example of the
216:
settings, for instance, players can participate in a game with some level of understanding of the probabilities of the possible outcomes and what specifically the outcomes lead to. For example, players know that there are six sides to a
176:
events. Consistent with this notion, it has been found the increasing the short term temptation (e.g., by showing outcomes from all options; or foregone payoffs) increases the underweighting of rare events in decisions from experience
67:
for both choices as well as the probabilities of all the outcomes within each choice. Typically, feedback is not given after a choice is selected. That is, the participant is not shown what consequences their selections led to.
179:
Since experience-based studies include multiple trials, participants must learn about the outcomes of the available choices. The participants must base their decisions on previous outcomes, so they must therefore rely on
48:
than the other. The other choice, then, offers a comparably improbable outcome. The specific payoffs or outcomes of the choices, in terms of the magnitude of their potential gains and losses, varies from study to study.
167:
studies usually involving responding to a limited number of trials or only one trial, recency effects likely do not have as much of an influence on decision making in these studies or may even be entirely irrelevant.
196:
tend to show opposite forms of responding. In described prospects, people tend to overweight the extreme outcomes such that they expect these probabilities to be more likely than they really are. Whereas in
151:
studies involve making the exact probabilities known to the participant. Since the participants here are immediately made aware of the rareness of an event, they are unlikely to undersample rare events.
111:. In the natural environment, people's decisions must be made without a clear description of the probabilities of the alternatives. Instead, decisions must be made by drawing upon past experiences. In 119:
from these choices, and they can only learn the outcomes from feedback after making their choices. Participants can only estimate the probabilities of the outcomes based on experiencing the outcomes.
212:
Typically in natural settings, however, peoples’ awareness of the probabilities of certain outcomes and their prior experience cannot be separated when they make decisions that involve risk. In
131:
aptly demonstrates the nature of the gap. Recall that description-based prospects lead to the reflection effect: people are risk averse for gains and risk seeking for losses. However,
221:, and that each side has a one in six chance of being rolled. However, a player's decisions in the game must also be influenced by his or her past experiences of playing the game. 135:
results in a reversal of the reflection effect such that people become risk seeking for gains and risk averse for losses. More specifically, the level of
115:, then, the outcomes and probabilities of the two possible choices are not initially presented to the participants. Instead, participants must 331: 261: 201:, people tend to underweight the probability of the extreme outcomes and therefore judge them as being even less likely to occur. 63:
are those where much of the information regarding each choice is clearly stated. That is, the participant is shown the potential
21: 321: 546:
Barron G, Erev I (2003). "Small feedback-based decisions and their limited correspondence to description-based decisions".
95:. When the choices involve losses, people tend to assign a higher value to the more improbable outcome; this is called the 705: 91:
tend to assign a higher value to sure or more probable outcomes when the choices involve gains; this is known as the
715: 710: 618:
Yechiam, E; Busemeyer, J (2006). "The effect of foregone payoffs on underweighting small probability events".
654: 555: 434: 356:"Of black swans and tossed coins:Is the description-experience gap in risky choice limited to rare events" 685: 64: 367: 659: 560: 439: 600: 523: 452: 302: 107:
Previous studies focusing on description-based prospects suffered from one drawback: the lack of
645:
Ludvig EA, Madan CR, Spetch ML (2014). "Extreme outcomes sway risky decisions from experience".
583:
Hogarth RM, Einhorn HJ (1992). "Order effects in belief updating: The belief-adjustment model".
482: 419: 515: 395: 327: 294: 108: 664: 627: 592: 565: 505: 497: 444: 385: 375: 284: 276: 510: 289: 235: 230: 76: 69: 44:
the alternatives without having any prior knowledge of the consequences of their choices.
25: 371: 390: 355: 160: 188:
To reiterate, prospect theory offers sound explanations for how people behave towards
699: 596: 501: 171:
Another variable which may be driving the results for the experience-based decisions
604: 527: 143:
One factor that may contribute to the gap is the nature of the sampling task. In a
306: 690: 380: 136: 86:
when the two possible choices both offer a chance to receive a certain reward.
37: 280: 116: 519: 399: 298: 32:
depending on whether their decisions are made towards clearly outlined and
483:"Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice" 218: 213: 172: 29: 456: 668: 181: 631: 569: 448: 72:
guides much of what is currently known regarding described choices.
99:
because it leads to the opposite result of the certainty effect.
140:
contribute to the gap; some of which will be discussed below.
28:. The gap refers to the observed differences in people's 420:"Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk" 320:Eysenck, Michael W.; Keane, Mark T. (2020-03-09). 686:An introduction to Prospect Theory (econport.com) 262:"The description-experience gap in risky choice" 481:Hertwig R, Barron G, Weber EU, Erev I (2004). 8: 323:Cognitive Psychology: A Student's Handbook 658: 559: 509: 438: 389: 379: 288: 255: 253: 251: 691:Prospect Theory (behaviouralfiance.net) 247: 647:Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 620:Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 548:Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 541: 539: 537: 476: 474: 472: 470: 468: 466: 413: 411: 409: 349: 347: 345: 343: 7: 14: 204:A highly relevant example of the 502:10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.00715.x 159:studies may be the result of a 511:11858/00-001M-0000-002E-57CE-F 418:Kahneman D, Tversky A (1979). 290:11858/00-001M-0000-002E-57C8-C 192:. However, the results from 1: 354:Ludvig EA, Spetch ML (2011). 597:10.1016/0010-0285(92)90002-J 381:10.1371/journal.pone.0020262 269:Trends in Cognitive Sciences 260:Hertwig, R; Erev, I (2009). 190:description-based prospects 732: 281:10.1016/j.tics.2009.09.004 206:description-experience gap 194:experience-based prospects 133:experience-based prospects 18:description-experience gap 129:reverse reflection effect 113:experience-based studies 82:Prospects are termed as 40:or whether they simply 22:experimental behavioral 490:Psychological Science 199:experienced prospects 706:Behavioral economics 585:Cognitive Psychology 326:. Psychology Press. 137:risk-taking behavior 372:2011PLoSO...620262L 20:is a phenomenon in 333:978-1-351-05850-6 165:description-based 155:The results from 149:description-based 145:sampling paradigm 109:external validity 97:reflection effect 57:Description-based 723: 673: 672: 669:10.1002/bdm.1792 662: 642: 636: 635: 615: 609: 608: 580: 574: 573: 563: 543: 532: 531: 513: 487: 478: 461: 460: 442: 424: 415: 404: 403: 393: 383: 351: 338: 337: 317: 311: 310: 292: 266: 257: 157:experience-based 93:certainty effect 59:alternatives or 731: 730: 726: 725: 724: 722: 721: 720: 716:Decision theory 711:Prospect theory 696: 695: 682: 677: 676: 660:10.1.1.718.7150 644: 643: 639: 632:10.1002/bdm.509 617: 616: 612: 582: 581: 577: 570:10.1002/bdm.443 561:10.1.1.320.4812 545: 544: 535: 485: 480: 479: 464: 449:10.2307/1914185 440:10.1.1.407.1910 422: 417: 416: 407: 353: 352: 341: 334: 319: 318: 314: 264: 259: 258: 249: 244: 236:Prospect theory 231:Decision theory 227: 105: 77:prospect theory 70:Prospect theory 54: 26:decision making 12: 11: 5: 729: 727: 719: 718: 713: 708: 698: 697: 694: 693: 688: 681: 680:External links 678: 675: 674: 653:(2): 146–156. 637: 610: 575: 533: 462: 405: 339: 332: 312: 275:(12): 517–23. 246: 245: 243: 240: 239: 238: 233: 226: 223: 161:recency effect 104: 101: 53: 50: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 728: 717: 714: 712: 709: 707: 704: 703: 701: 692: 689: 687: 684: 683: 679: 670: 666: 661: 656: 652: 648: 641: 638: 633: 629: 625: 621: 614: 611: 606: 602: 598: 594: 590: 586: 579: 576: 571: 567: 562: 557: 554:(3): 215–23. 553: 549: 542: 540: 538: 534: 529: 525: 521: 517: 512: 507: 503: 499: 496:(8): 534–39. 495: 491: 484: 477: 475: 473: 471: 469: 467: 463: 458: 454: 450: 446: 441: 436: 433:(2): 263–92. 432: 428: 421: 414: 412: 410: 406: 401: 397: 392: 387: 382: 377: 373: 369: 366:(6): e20262. 365: 361: 357: 350: 348: 346: 344: 340: 335: 329: 325: 324: 316: 313: 308: 304: 300: 296: 291: 286: 282: 278: 274: 270: 263: 256: 254: 252: 248: 241: 237: 234: 232: 229: 228: 224: 222: 220: 215: 210: 207: 202: 200: 195: 191: 186: 183: 177: 174: 169: 166: 162: 158: 153: 150: 146: 141: 138: 134: 130: 124: 120: 118: 114: 110: 102: 100: 98: 94: 89: 85: 80: 78: 75:According to 73: 71: 66: 62: 58: 51: 49: 45: 43: 39: 38:probabilities 36:outcomes and 35: 31: 27: 23: 19: 650: 646: 640: 623: 619: 613: 588: 584: 578: 551: 547: 493: 489: 430: 427:Econometrica 426: 363: 359: 322: 315: 272: 268: 211: 205: 203: 198: 193: 189: 187: 178: 170: 164: 156: 154: 148: 144: 142: 132: 128: 125: 121: 112: 106: 96: 92: 87: 83: 81: 74: 60: 56: 55: 46: 41: 33: 17: 15: 52:Description 24:studies of 700:Categories 242:References 103:Experience 42:experience 655:CiteSeerX 556:CiteSeerX 435:CiteSeerX 61:prospects 34:described 626:: 1–16. 605:54272129 591:: 1–55. 528:12977034 520:15270998 400:21673807 360:PLOS ONE 299:19836292 225:See also 214:gambling 173:paradigm 65:outcomes 30:behavior 457:1914185 391:3105996 368:Bibcode 307:2190783 657:  603:  558:  526:  518:  455:  437:  398:  388:  330:  305:  297:  182:memory 117:sample 88:Losses 601:S2CID 524:S2CID 486:(PDF) 453:JSTOR 423:(PDF) 303:S2CID 265:(PDF) 84:gains 516:PMID 396:PMID 328:ISBN 295:PMID 16:The 665:doi 628:doi 593:doi 566:doi 506:hdl 498:doi 445:doi 386:PMC 376:doi 285:hdl 277:doi 219:die 702:: 663:. 651:27 649:. 624:19 622:. 599:. 589:24 587:. 564:. 552:16 550:. 536:^ 522:. 514:. 504:. 494:15 492:. 488:. 465:^ 451:. 443:. 431:47 429:. 425:. 408:^ 394:. 384:. 374:. 362:. 358:. 342:^ 301:. 293:. 283:. 273:13 271:. 267:. 250:^ 671:. 667:: 634:. 630:: 607:. 595:: 572:. 568:: 530:. 508:: 500:: 459:. 447:: 402:. 378:: 370:: 364:6 336:. 309:. 287:: 279::

Index

experimental behavioral
decision making
behavior
probabilities
outcomes
Prospect theory
prospect theory
external validity
sample
risk-taking behavior
recency effect
paradigm
memory
gambling
die
Decision theory
Prospect theory



"The description-experience gap in risky choice"
doi
10.1016/j.tics.2009.09.004
hdl
11858/00-001M-0000-002E-57C8-C
PMID
19836292
S2CID
2190783
Cognitive Psychology: A Student's Handbook

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.