Knowledge (XXG)

Imperative logic

Source 📝

1293: 1283: 33: 186:
Here is the dilemma. Either arguments containing imperatives can be valid or not. On the one hand, if such arguments can be valid, we need a new or expanded account of logical validity and the concomitant details. Providing such an account has proved challenging. On the other hand, if such arguments
372:
held that no declarative conclusion can be validly drawn from a set of premises which cannot validly be drawn from the declaratives among them alone. There is no consensus among logicians about the truth or falsity of these (or similar) claims and mixed imperative and declarative inference remains
308:
be fulfilled in an acceptable possible world; The conclusion "It is obligatory to clean your room or burn the house down" does not falsify the premise "It is obligatory to clean your room". In addition, based on the context, it may also be true that "It is obligatory to not burn the house down", in
182:
However, an argument is valid if the conclusion follows from the premises. This means the premises give us reason to believe the conclusion, or, alternatively, the truth of the premises determines truth of the conclusion. Since imperatives are neither true nor false and since they are not proper
296:
highlights the challenge faced by anyone who wants to modify or add to the standard account of validity. The challenge is what we mean by a valid imperative inference. For valid declarative inference, the premises give you a reason to believe the conclusion. One might think that for imperative
187:
cannot be valid (either because such arguments are all invalid or because validity is not a notion that applies to imperatives), then our logical intuitions regarding the above argument (and others similar to it) are mistaken. Since either answer seems problematic, this has come to be known as
232:
to an argument with imperatives such that a truth-value can be assigned to the proposition. For example, it may be hard to assign a truth-value to the argument "Take all the books off the table!", but
271:
under the scope of an imperative operator leads to unintuitive (or apparently absurd) results. When applied to simple declaratives, the result appears to be valid deduction.
381:
Aside from intrinsic interest, imperative logic has other applications. The use of imperatives in moral theory should make imperative inference an important subject for
297:
inference, the premises give you a reason to do as the conclusion says; While Ross's paradox seems to suggest otherwise, its severity has been subject of much debate.
250: 230: 252:("take all the books off the table"), which means "It is obligatory to take all the books off the table", can be assigned a truth-value, because it is in the 729: 442:
Frege, G. (1892) 'On sense and reference', in Geach and Black (eds.) Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege Oxford: Blackwell.
877: 570: 544: 148:
or more generally what role truth and falsity play in their semantics. Thus, there is almost no consensus on any aspect of imperative logic.
620: 339:
In this case, all the sentences making up the argument are imperatives. Not all imperative inferences are of this kind. Consider again:
938: 368:
held that no imperative conclusion can be validly drawn from a set of premises which does not contain at least one imperative. While
907: 744: 116: 669: 54: 47: 1163: 592: 490: 97: 309:
which case any acceptable possible world must have "Your room is cleaned" and "The house is not burnt down" to be both true.
69: 1156: 980: 468: 76: 810: 196: 578: 320:, in which disjunction introduction leads to absurd conclusions when applied under the scope of a possibility modal. 192: 932: 872: 1000: 815: 83: 43: 975: 183:
objects of belief, none of the standard accounts of logical validity apply to arguments containing imperatives.
1095: 268: 361:
Notice that this argument is composed of both imperatives and declaratives and has an imperative conclusion.
65: 1223: 1183: 1060: 857: 775: 679: 674: 613: 532: 1317: 1100: 990: 1141: 1085: 970: 805: 699: 403: 317: 1258: 1243: 1218: 1213: 1065: 1263: 1248: 1238: 1203: 1151: 1080: 995: 867: 862: 785: 780: 709: 1025: 985: 949: 882: 749: 719: 714: 684: 649: 644: 305: 1296: 1253: 1233: 1173: 1146: 944: 897: 887: 800: 664: 606: 1198: 845: 840: 830: 795: 704: 1286: 1268: 1208: 1188: 1178: 1105: 1090: 1010: 1005: 835: 790: 659: 566: 540: 408: 365: 90: 1228: 1193: 1168: 1120: 1045: 1020: 1015: 917: 892: 473: 157: 141: 1136: 1115: 1110: 1070: 912: 902: 739: 734: 724: 689: 137: 1075: 1050: 1040: 1035: 965: 765: 654: 514: 512:
Hare, Richard M. (1967). Some alleged differences between imperatives and indicatives.
477: 423: 235: 215: 1311: 1055: 922: 770: 398: 301: 209: 203: 852: 825: 820: 145: 282:
However, a similar inference does not seem to be valid for imperatives. Consider:
17: 1030: 565:(2nd ed.). Taylor & Francis. Chapter 12: Deontic and Imperative Logic. 253: 32: 453: 418: 413: 386: 369: 313: 264: 630: 382: 364:
Mixed inferences are of special interest to logicians. For instance,
598: 503:
Poincaré, Henri (1913). Dernières Pensées. Paris: Ernest Flammarion.
554: 160:. It seems that arguments with imperatives can be valid. Consider: 332:
P1. Do both of the following: wash the dishes and clean your room!
133: 694: 602: 26: 328:
The following is an example of a pure imperative inference:
206:, it received a more developed formulation by Jørgensen. 289:
C1. Therefore, clean your room or burn the house down!
238: 218: 557:, Entry for The International Encyclopedia of Ethics 202:
While this problem was first noted in a footnote by
1129: 958: 758: 637: 278:
C1. Therefore, the room is clean or grass is green.
244: 224: 451:Jørgensen, J. (1938) 'Imperatives and logic', 212:takes the approach of adding a modal operator 614: 267:observed that applying the classical rule of 144:, it is not clear whether imperatives denote 8: 1282: 621: 607: 599: 312:Some strands of this debate connect it to 488:Ross, A. (1944) ‘Imperatives and Logic’, 466:Ross, A. (1941) ‘Imperatives and Logic’, 237: 217: 117:Learn how and when to remove this message 927: 435: 156:One of a logic's principal concerns is 53:Please improve this article by adding 343:P1. Take all the books off the table! 304:requires that all obligations in the 164:P1. Take all the books off the table! 7: 939:What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 478:10.1111/j.1755-2567.1941.tb00034.x 25: 1292: 1291: 1281: 31: 335:C1. Therefore, clean your room! 577:Covers mostly the approach of 1: 55:secondary or tertiary sources 553:Peter B. M. Vranas (2010), 302:semantics for Deontic logic 1334: 1277: 561:Harry J. Gensler (2010). 409:List of Logical Paradoxes 355:Foundations of Arithmetic 348:Foundations of Arithmetic 176:Foundations of Arithmetic 169:Foundations of Arithmetic 595:, University of Virginia 269:disjunction introduction 858:Paradoxes of set theory 533:Charles Leonard Hamblin 259: 151: 555:IMPERATIVES, LOGIC OF* 318:paradox of free choice 275:P1. The room is clean. 246: 226: 42:relies excessively on 579:Héctor-Neri Castañeda 563:Introduction to Logic 491:Philosophy of Science 404:Free choice inference 247: 227: 1224:Kavka's toxin puzzle 996:Income and fertility 353:C1. Therefore, take 286:P1. Clean your room! 236: 216: 174:C1. Therefore, take 883:Temperature paradox 806:Free choice paradox 670:Fitch's knowability 591:Mitchell S. Green, 539:. Basil Blackwell. 306:domain of discourse 189:Jørgensen's dilemma 152:Jørgensen's dilemma 1259:Prisoner's dilemma 945:Heat death paradox 933:Unexpected hanging 898:Chicken or the egg 242: 222: 66:"Imperative logic" 18:Ross' paradox 1305: 1304: 976:Arrow information 572:978-0-415-99650-1 546:978-0-631-15193-7 245:{\displaystyle O} 225:{\displaystyle O} 140:. In contrast to 127: 126: 119: 101: 16:(Redirected from 1325: 1295: 1294: 1285: 1284: 1096:Service recovery 950:Olbers's paradox 650:Buridan's bridge 623: 616: 609: 600: 593:Imperative Logic 576: 550: 519: 510: 504: 501: 495: 486: 480: 464: 458: 449: 443: 440: 350:is on the table. 324:Mixed inferences 251: 249: 248: 243: 231: 229: 228: 223: 193:Jørgen Jørgensen 171:is on the table. 158:logical validity 132:is the field of 130:Imperative logic 122: 115: 111: 108: 102: 100: 59: 35: 27: 21: 1333: 1332: 1328: 1327: 1326: 1324: 1323: 1322: 1308: 1307: 1306: 1301: 1273: 1184:Decision-making 1130:Decision theory 1125: 954: 878:Hilbert's Hotel 811:Grelling–Nelson 754: 633: 627: 588: 573: 560: 547: 531: 528: 526:Further reading 523: 522: 511: 507: 502: 498: 487: 483: 465: 461: 450: 446: 441: 437: 432: 395: 379: 326: 262: 254:indicative mood 234: 233: 214: 213: 154: 136:concerned with 123: 112: 106: 103: 60: 58: 52: 48:primary sources 36: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 1331: 1329: 1321: 1320: 1310: 1309: 1303: 1302: 1300: 1299: 1289: 1278: 1275: 1274: 1272: 1271: 1266: 1261: 1256: 1251: 1246: 1241: 1236: 1231: 1226: 1221: 1216: 1211: 1206: 1201: 1196: 1191: 1186: 1181: 1176: 1171: 1166: 1161: 1160: 1159: 1154: 1149: 1139: 1133: 1131: 1127: 1126: 1124: 1123: 1118: 1113: 1108: 1103: 1101:St. Petersburg 1098: 1093: 1088: 1083: 1078: 1073: 1068: 1063: 1058: 1053: 1048: 1043: 1038: 1033: 1028: 1023: 1018: 1013: 1008: 1003: 998: 993: 988: 983: 978: 973: 968: 962: 960: 956: 955: 953: 952: 947: 942: 935: 930: 925: 920: 915: 910: 905: 900: 895: 890: 885: 880: 875: 870: 865: 860: 855: 850: 849: 848: 843: 838: 833: 828: 818: 813: 808: 803: 798: 793: 788: 783: 778: 773: 768: 762: 760: 756: 755: 753: 752: 747: 742: 737: 732: 730:Rule-following 727: 722: 717: 712: 707: 702: 697: 692: 687: 682: 677: 672: 667: 662: 657: 655:Dream argument 652: 647: 641: 639: 635: 634: 628: 626: 625: 618: 611: 603: 597: 596: 587: 586:External links 584: 583: 582: 571: 558: 551: 545: 527: 524: 521: 520: 518:, 76, 309-326. 505: 496: 481: 459: 444: 434: 433: 431: 428: 427: 426: 424:Temporal logic 421: 416: 411: 406: 401: 394: 391: 378: 375: 366:Henri Poincaré 359: 358: 357:off the table! 351: 344: 337: 336: 333: 325: 322: 294:Ross's paradox 291: 290: 287: 280: 279: 276: 261: 260:Ross's paradox 258: 241: 221: 191:, named after 180: 179: 178:off the table! 172: 165: 153: 150: 125: 124: 39: 37: 30: 24: 14: 13: 10: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1330: 1319: 1318:Deontic logic 1316: 1315: 1313: 1298: 1290: 1288: 1280: 1279: 1276: 1270: 1267: 1265: 1262: 1260: 1257: 1255: 1252: 1250: 1247: 1245: 1242: 1240: 1237: 1235: 1232: 1230: 1229:Morton's fork 1227: 1225: 1222: 1220: 1217: 1215: 1212: 1210: 1207: 1205: 1202: 1200: 1197: 1195: 1192: 1190: 1187: 1185: 1182: 1180: 1177: 1175: 1172: 1170: 1169:Buridan's ass 1167: 1165: 1162: 1158: 1155: 1153: 1150: 1148: 1145: 1144: 1143: 1142:Apportionment 1140: 1138: 1135: 1134: 1132: 1128: 1122: 1119: 1117: 1114: 1112: 1109: 1107: 1104: 1102: 1099: 1097: 1094: 1092: 1089: 1087: 1084: 1082: 1079: 1077: 1074: 1072: 1069: 1067: 1064: 1062: 1059: 1057: 1054: 1052: 1049: 1047: 1044: 1042: 1039: 1037: 1034: 1032: 1029: 1027: 1024: 1022: 1019: 1017: 1014: 1012: 1009: 1007: 1004: 1002: 1001:Downs–Thomson 999: 997: 994: 992: 989: 987: 984: 982: 979: 977: 974: 972: 969: 967: 964: 963: 961: 957: 951: 948: 946: 943: 940: 936: 934: 931: 929: 926: 924: 921: 919: 918:Plato's beard 916: 914: 911: 909: 906: 904: 901: 899: 896: 894: 891: 889: 886: 884: 881: 879: 876: 874: 871: 869: 866: 864: 861: 859: 856: 854: 851: 847: 844: 842: 839: 837: 834: 832: 829: 827: 824: 823: 822: 819: 817: 816:Kleene–Rosser 814: 812: 809: 807: 804: 802: 799: 797: 794: 792: 789: 787: 784: 782: 779: 777: 774: 772: 769: 767: 764: 763: 761: 757: 751: 748: 746: 743: 741: 740:Theseus' ship 738: 736: 733: 731: 728: 726: 723: 721: 718: 716: 713: 711: 708: 706: 703: 701: 700:Mere addition 698: 696: 693: 691: 688: 686: 683: 681: 678: 676: 673: 671: 668: 666: 663: 661: 658: 656: 653: 651: 648: 646: 643: 642: 640: 638:Philosophical 636: 632: 624: 619: 617: 612: 610: 605: 604: 601: 594: 590: 589: 585: 580: 574: 568: 564: 559: 556: 552: 548: 542: 538: 534: 530: 529: 525: 517: 516: 509: 506: 500: 497: 493: 492: 485: 482: 479: 475: 471: 470: 463: 460: 456: 455: 448: 445: 439: 436: 429: 425: 422: 420: 417: 415: 412: 410: 407: 405: 402: 400: 399:Deontic logic 397: 396: 392: 390: 388: 384: 376: 374: 371: 367: 362: 356: 352: 349: 345: 342: 341: 340: 334: 331: 330: 329: 323: 321: 319: 315: 310: 307: 303: 298: 295: 288: 285: 284: 283: 277: 274: 273: 272: 270: 266: 257: 255: 239: 219: 211: 210:Deontic logic 207: 205: 200: 198: 194: 190: 184: 177: 173: 170: 166: 163: 162: 161: 159: 149: 147: 143: 139: 135: 131: 121: 118: 110: 99: 96: 92: 89: 85: 82: 78: 75: 71: 68: –  67: 63: 62:Find sources: 56: 50: 49: 45: 40:This article 38: 34: 29: 28: 19: 1249:Preparedness 1081:Productivity 1061:Mandeville's 853:Opposite Day 781:Burali-Forti 776:Bhartrhari's 562: 536: 513: 508: 499: 489: 484: 467: 462: 452: 447: 438: 380: 377:Applications 363: 360: 354: 347: 338: 327: 311: 299: 293: 292: 281: 263: 208: 201: 188: 185: 181: 175: 168: 155: 146:propositions 142:declaratives 129: 128: 113: 107:October 2012 104: 94: 87: 80: 73: 61: 41: 1179:Condorcet's 1031:Giffen good 991:Competition 745:White horse 720:Omnipotence 537:Imperatives 414:Speech acts 138:imperatives 1254:Prevention 1244:Parrondo's 1234:Navigation 1219:Inventor's 1214:Hedgehog's 1174:Chainstore 1157:Population 1152:New states 1086:Prosperity 1066:Mayfield's 908:Entailment 888:Barbershop 801:Epimenides 494:11: 30–46. 472:7: 53–71. 457:7: 288-98. 454:Erkenntnis 430:References 419:Pragmatics 387:metaethics 77:newspapers 44:references 1269:Willpower 1264:Tolerance 1239:Newcomb's 1204:Fredkin's 1091:Scitovsky 1011:Edgeworth 1006:Easterlin 971:Antitrust 868:Russell's 863:Richard's 836:Pinocchio 791:Crocodile 710:Newcomb's 680:Goodman's 675:Free will 660:Epicurean 631:paradoxes 370:R.M. Hare 314:Hans Kamp 1312:Category 1297:Category 1194:Ellsberg 1046:Leontief 1026:Gibson's 1021:European 1016:Ellsberg 986:Braess's 981:Bertrand 959:Economic 893:Catch-22 873:Socratic 715:Nihilism 685:Hedonism 645:Analysis 629:Notable 535:(1987). 393:See also 265:Alf Ross 1199:Fenno's 1164:Arrow's 1147:Alabama 1137:Abilene 1116:Tullock 1071:Metzler 913:Lottery 903:Drinker 846:Yablo's 841:Quine's 796:Curry's 759:Logical 735:Sorites 725:Preface 705:Moore's 690:Liberal 665:Fiction 469:Theoria 373:vexed. 91:scholar 1106:Thrift 1076:Plenty 1051:Lerner 1041:Jevons 1036:Icarus 966:Allais 928:Ross's 766:Barber 750:Zeno's 695:Meno's 569:  543:  383:ethics 93:  86:  79:  72:  64:  1209:Green 1189:Downs 1121:Value 1056:Lucas 923:Raven 831:No-no 786:Court 771:Berry 204:Frege 134:logic 98:JSTOR 84:books 1287:List 1111:Toil 826:Card 821:Liar 567:ISBN 541:ISBN 515:Mind 385:and 346:P2. 300:The 167:P2. 70:news 474:doi 316:'s 199:). 46:to 1314:: 389:. 256:. 197:da 57:. 941:" 937:" 622:e 615:t 608:v 581:. 575:. 549:. 476:: 240:O 220:O 195:( 120:) 114:( 109:) 105:( 95:· 88:· 81:· 74:· 51:. 20:)

Index

Ross' paradox

references
primary sources
secondary or tertiary sources
"Imperative logic"
news
newspapers
books
scholar
JSTOR
Learn how and when to remove this message
logic
imperatives
declaratives
propositions
logical validity
Jørgen Jørgensen
da
Frege
Deontic logic
indicative mood
Alf Ross
disjunction introduction
semantics for Deontic logic
domain of discourse
Hans Kamp
paradox of free choice
Henri Poincaré
R.M. Hare

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.